ISSN 1393-614X Minerva - An Internet
Journal of Philosophy Vol. 13 2009
________________________________________________
Euthyphro and the Open Question Timo Kajamies |
In
his excellent introduction to metaethics, Alexander Miller argues that there
are affinities between G. E. Moore's open-question argument and Socrates’
argumentation in Euthyphro dialogue.
Miller is also led to ask how Moore's argument can be disdained without being
unsympathetic to Socrates’ argument. This paper answers to Miller's question by
showing that the two arguments are quite different. It is also argued that the
two arguments merit different assessments: one may well appreciate Socrates’
reasoning and yet be unconvinced by Moore's.
1. Introduction
In Principia Ethica, G. E. Moore argues that moral concepts, such as
the concept of good or that of evil, cannot be reductively analyzed in terms of
naturalistic concepts, such as the concept of desire or that of aversion.
Moore's argument to this effect has been coined 'the open-question argument'.
In Plato's Euthyphro, Socrates
argues, against Euthyphro, that the concept of good cannot be reductively
analyzed through the concept of God's love. In his excellent introduction to
metaethics, Alexander Miller (2004, 15n4) is struck by the impression that
there are affinities between the open-question argument and the argument
against Euthyphro. Moreover, because the former argument may be disdained
without being unsympathetic to the latter, Miller is led to ask whence the
differing assessments, especially if the two arguments are really identical.
So, are they?[1]
Let me give some further motivation
for the question. First of all, it is clear that there are strong theoretical
affinities between Moore's and Plato's views; Moore's ethics can be classified
as Platonistic (Moore 1991, lecture V; Regan 1991, xxxi-xxxii), and both Plato
and Moore believe that 'good' is an unanalysable concept.
Furthermore, both Moore and Socrates of Euthyphro
set forth an argument to the effect that an attempt to define good in a given
way goes amiss. Besides, both Moore and Socrates can be understood as pursuing
real definitions as opposed to nominal definitions. Given these grounds, the
question quite naturally arises as to what the relation between the
open-question argument and the argument against Euthyphro is.
In this paper I argue for the view
that the two arguments are quite different. Moreover, I argue that they do
merit differing assessments: one may well appreciate Socrates’ argument against
Euthyphro and yet be wholly unconvinced by Moore's argument against naturalism.
I shall begin by reconstructing the
argument against Euthyphro and then the open-question argument. With the help
of these reconstructions, I hope to bring the two arguments structurally as
close to each other as possible. An important difference becomes clear, though.
The disparity pertains to conceptual substitution – it is governed by different
principles in the two arguments, respectively. Finally, I argue that a more
fundamental divergence is there to be found as well. Namely, the so-called
paradox of analysis does not have to be a problematic issue for a proponent of
the argument against Euthyphro in a way that it is for the defender of Moore's
open-question argument.[2]
1. A Reconstruction of the Argument Against
Euthyphro
Let me
now formulate Socrates’ argument against Euthyphro. The general outline of my
treatment of the argument against Euthyphro is due to Mark Johnston account
(see Johnston 1993, 118-119), discussed in Miller 1995, on which I will heavily
rely here. The basic assumption invoked in the present reading is that both
Socrates and Euthyphro agree that something is good if and only if it is loved
by God; what they disagree about is the correct interpretation of this fact
(cf. Miller 1995, 858). In a nutshell, Euthyphro proposes that the above
equivalence is conceptually necessary, whereas the argument against Euthyphro
purports to show that it is not (cf. Miller 1995, 858-859).
According
to Socrates, then, the following equivalence is not conceptually necessary:
(EE) For all x, x is good if an only if x is loved by God.
An important role in the argument
against Euthyphro is played by what can be called the Euthyphro dilemma (Plato 1997, 9e):
Does God love x
because x is good, or is x good because God loves x?
As an answer, Euthyphro assents to
the following claim (Plato 1997, 10e):
(EG) For all x,
God loves x because x is good (and it is not the case that x is good because
God loves x).
The
'because' here is the 'because' of explanation, as distinguished from mere
conceptual articulation.[3] Socrates and
Euthyphro agree that (EG) does not articulate the concept of God's love.
Instead, (EG) is genuinely explanatory: God's love for x can be explained by
appeal to x's goodness.
Obviously
enough, for a statement to be a potentially genuine explanation, it must not be
trivially true; a statement that cannot be informative due to its literal
meaning, will not qualify as a potential explanation. Following Johnston,
Miller (1995, 858) calls this type of statement an 'explanatory solecism'. For
instance, the statement "Donald loves Peg because Donald loves Peg"
is an explanatory solecism, since it is trivially true; its literal meaning
makes it uninformative.
Now,
Socrates argues that, when read as a conceptually necessary truth, (EE) is in
tension with (EG). The two statements are in tension, since the following
substitution principle holds (cf. Miller 1995, 859):
(SS)
Substitution of conceptual equivalents cannot turn a genuinely explanatory statement
into an explanatory solecism.
According
to the present interpretation, Socrates argues that since (EE) allows a
substitution that turns a genuinely explanatory statement into an explanatory
solecism, (EE) cannot be conceptually necessary. Namely, the substitution turns
(EG) into
(ES) For all x, God loves x because God loves x.
2. A Reconstruction of the Open-Question
Argument
I shall
next propose a reconstruction of Moore's open-question argument, presented in §§12-13 of Principia
Ethica (Moore 1954). First of all, I believe Moore, while arguing that good resists naturalistic analysis, is trying to
show that the predicate 'good' is not conceptually equivalent to any
naturalistic predicate 'N' (e.g. Moore 1942, 661). He thus argues that the following equivalence is not a conceptually
necessary truth:
(EM) For all x, x is good if and only if x is N.
Now,
according to Moore, the following question is genuinely open:
(OQ) Is an x which is N also good?
Obviously
enough, there are open questions and closed questions. A clear case of a closed
question would be a question that can be answered just by considering its
literal meaning. For instance, the question "Are all black ravens
black?" is obviously closed, since the literal meaning of it already gives
the answer. The question "Are all black ravens greedy for glittery
things?", in turn, is an open question, since answering that question
requires information not due to merely understanding that question. In
distinguishing open questions and closed questions, Moore emphasizes the idea of intelligibility.
What he calls closed questions are those that are unintelligible, whereas the
open questions are intelligible; it makes sense to ask an open question, but it
does not make sense to ask a closed question (Moore 1954, §13).
The gist
of Moore's argument, I find, is that when (EM) is read as a conceptual truth,
it is in tension with (OQ). The tension surfaces when the following
substitution principle is accepted:
(SM) Substitution of conceptual equivalents cannot turn a genuinely open
question into a closed one.
According
to the interpretation presented here, Moore argues that since (EM) allows a
substitution that turns a genuinely open question into a closed one, (EM)
cannot represent a conceptual truth. Namely, the substitution turns the open
(OQ) into the closed question (CQ):
(CQ) Is an x which is good also good?
3. The Open-Question Argument and the Paradox of Analysis
The view that the open-question
argument falls prey to the paradox of analysis has been set forth by various
scholars (see e.g. Fumerton 1983, 477-479). To my knowledge, however, the
comparison between the open-question argument and the argument against
Euthyphro from the point of view of the paradox of analysis is missing. This is
what I shall focus in on next.
Now, take any analysis of the form
"A is B", where A is what is analyzed and B what is offered as the
analysis. Suppose 'A' and 'B' have the same meaning. The analysis is then
correct, but only expresses a trivial identity statement "A is A".
However, if 'A' and 'B' do not mean the same, the analysis does not seem to be
correct. Therefore, it seems that no analysis can be both correct and
informative. What we have here is the paradox of analysis.
A crucial concept invoked in the
paradox of analysis, obviously, is the concept of analysis. What does it mean
to provide an analysis? In particular, what does Moore say about this? I read
him as holding that the pursuit of defining good is the pursuit of finding a real definition of good, as
distinguished from a nominal
definition (e.g. Moore 1954, §6). Accordingly, Moore is dealing with the
question of how and whether good can be metaphysically
analyzed. However, Moore (e.g. 1942, 661) understands analysis as conceptual analysis. Therefore, I read
Moore as holding that to provide a correct metaphysical analysis is to provide
a correct conceptual analysis.
Now, the
equivalence
(EM) For all x, x
is good if an only if x is N
qualifies as a correct metaphysical
analysis of good only if the equivalence is metaphysically necessary. However,
Moore's conception of analysis requires that the equivalence represents a
correct metaphysical analysis of good only if the equivalence is also
conceptually necessary. That is, such equivalence should be true simply as a
matter of meaning of the terms involved in it.
This being the case, an equivalence
such as
(K) For all x, x
is water if and only if x is H2O,
supposing that it represents a
correct analysis, should not state anything that is not involved in
(K') For all x,
x is water if and only if x is water.
So, correct analyses should be
trivially true ― hopelessly uninformative ― since they do not state
anything that is not involved in some uninformative statement such as (K').
Nevertheless, correct definitions do not always seem trivial. For instance, it
is quite plausible to hold that if (K) is true, it is necessarily true (Kripke
1972, 314, 320-321; Putnam 1975, 233), and hence it may be held to give us a
correct analysis of what it is to be water, by telling us that water is the
same stuff as H2O. Furthermore, (K) is obviously informative; it
takes a lot of scientific effort to discover that the equivalence holds.
Let me now formulate the way in
which I believe the paradox of analysis is a serious problem for a proponent of
the open-question argument. To start with, Moore can be read to claim that
correct analyses are to be represented by means of conceptually necessary
equivalences, as noted above. And conceptual necessities coincide with
metaphysical necessities. The crucial question now becomes "How can there
be any necessary equivalences that are not trivially true?" I shall next
argue that the substitution principle (SM), coupled with Moore's conception of
analysis, prevents there from being such equivalences.
In order to make my point clearer,
let me first make a distinction between a question and its corresponding
equivalence. Consider the following question:
Q: Is an x that
is A also B?
Now, for each Q-type question we
can formulate the following kind of equivalence:
E: For all x, x
is A if and only if x is B.
I shall call E the 'corresponding
equivalence' of Q, and Q the 'corresponding question' of E.
It is easy to see that, for each
Q-type question, there is an equivalence E that allows a substitution that
results in a closed question. Namely, E turns Q into
Q': Is an x
that is A also A?
Keeping in mind that a necessary
equivalence always closes its corresponding question, we see that the genuine
openness of a question straightforwardly implies that its corresponding
equivalence is not necessary. In particular, the equivalence is then neither
conceptually nor metaphysically necessary. Hence, the open-question argument
presupposes that an equivalence can represent a correct analysis only if its
corresponding question is closed and hence unintelligible. However, the
intelligibility of a question is a prerequisite for the informativeness of its
corresponding equivalence. Therefore, Moore seems committed to the view that
the substitution principle (SM), invoked in the open-question argument,
prevents there from being informative necessary equivalences.[4]
4. The Argument Against Euthyphro and the Paradox of Analysis
I shall next argue that the
argument against Euthyphro can be defended without falling prey to the paradox
of analysis. I will not be claiming that Socrates would have provided such
defense; my treatment will be, from an ancient point of view, unquestionably
anachronistic. However, I hope to succeed in pointing out that there is ample
room for a theory whose proponent might put the argument against Euthyphro into
good use without being committed to the claim that there cannot be any
non-trivially but necessarily true equivalence concerning good.
One crucial tenet in the moral
semantics in question is the distinction between metaphysical necessities and
conceptual necessities. The above example of water as stuff composed of H2O
molecules is a case in point. 'Water', as understood here, is a rigid
designator; it designates the same kind of stuff – stuff composed of H2O
molecules – in each possible world in which it exists. The equivalence
(K) For all x,
x is water if and only if x is H2O
is thus metaphysically necessary. However,
the equivalence is not conceptually necessary, since 'water' and 'stuff
composed of H2O molecules' are not synonymous.
Notice that a proponent of the
above sketch of semantic theory for natural kind terms may formulate an
argument that closely resembles the argument against Euthyphro, in order to
show that the concept of water resists analysis into the concept of stuff
composed of H2O molecules. Importantly, one may argue in this
fashion and still hold that the equivalence (K) is necessarily true, without committing herself to the view that the
equivalence is trivially true. One
might proceed as follows.
First, one might single out the
purported conceptual analysis, represented by the equivalence (K). Then one
could accept the following genuinely explanatory statement:
(EW) For all x,
x is water because x is composed of H2O molecules.
One could then argue that (K) and
(EW) are in tension, since the substitution principle (SS) holds. To repeat:
(SS)
Substitution of conceptual equivalents cannot turn a genuinely explanatory
statement into an explanatory solecism.
According
to the present argument, (K) allows a substitution that turns the genuinely
explanatory (EW) into the explanatory solecism:
(EH) For all x, x is water because x is water.
Hence,
(K) cannot be conceptually necessary. However, one may still hold that even if
(K) is not conceptually necessary, water and stuff composed of H2O
molecules are, so to speak, metaphysical equivalents. Finally, one may point
out that substitution of non-synonymous terms that nevertheless refer to
metaphysical equivalents does not preserve meaning, so no harm is done to (K)'s
informativeness. To wit, the substitution would trivialize (K) only if (EW) and
(EH) meant the same.
Along
quite similar lines, the proponent of the argument against Euthyphro may
criticize the attempt to analyze the concept of good in terms of that which is
loved by God. She may claim that moral terms, such as 'good', behave in an
important sense like natural kind terms, such as 'water'.[5] In particular, she
may argue that the equivalence
(EE) For all x, x is good if an only if x is loved by God
is
metaphysically but not conceptually necessary. Very well, she may say, (EE)
turns a genuinely explanatory statement into an explanatory solecism by
substitution, but this is not a problem for (EE)'s informativeness, since
meaning is not preserved by this substitution. Hence, the argument against
Euthyphro can in principle be accepted without being committed to the view that
the equivalence (EE) is trivially true. It can therefore be argued that the
paradox of analysis is not an issue for the proponent of the argument against
Euthyphro as it is for Moore's open-question argument.
5. Tracking Moral Truths
Obviously,
something more has to be said as to how the proponent of the argument against
Euthyphro can work out the distinction between metaphysical and conceptual
necessities. Mere analogy between moral terms and natural kind terms is not
enough.
In fact,
the analogy between moral terms and natural kind terms is not quite tenable in
the present context. However, this fact helps to steer in the right direction
when trying to describe how the proponent of the argument against Euthyphro
might understand the metaphysically necessary equivalence (EE). The analogy
ultimately fails because (EE), when read as a metaphysically necessary truth,
does not state that the properties being good and being loved by God are identical;
however, a metaphysically necessary equivalence involving natural kind terms,
according to the view discussed here, is read to express the view that some
properties, such as being water and being composed of H2O molecules,
are identical. The question now arises
as to how the proponent of the argument against Euthyphro explains the
metaphysical necessity of (EE). Let me now sketch an answer.
First,
consider a distinction, due to Crispin Wright, between views according to which
the most informed opinions are extension-reflecting
and views according to which the most informed opinions are extension-determining. Take, for
instance, Socrates’ belief that piety is good. On an extension-determining
view, the most informed opinions constitutively determine facts that confer truth or falsity upon Socrates’ belief.
On an extension-reflecting view, in turn, the most informed opinions track mind-independent facts that confer
truth or falsity upon Socrates’ belief (cf. Miller 1995, 859-860.) This
distinction helps to understand how the proponent of the argument against
Euthyphro may account for the metaphysical necessity of (EE). She may claim
that God is an infallible detector of good (Miller 1995, 858). (EE) may hence
be understood as a thesis expressing the view that in all possible worlds God
tracks moral truths without any error and loves all things that are good
independently of his judgment. However, the property of being loved by God is not identical with nor is it constitutive of
the property of being good. (EE) expresses
an extension-reflecting view of God’s moral beliefs, not an
extension-determining one.
To me
the above view seems very plausible, if the theistic framework involved in it
is accepted in the first place. When God is brought into the picture in moral
epistemology, it is very plausible to hold that he is morally omniscient. For
if God exists, his beliefs certainly are the most informed ones there could be.
And these beliefs of an omniscient being infallibly track moral facts that make
those beliefs true. Hence, I find it very plausible to hold that if the
equivalence (EE) is true, it is true in all possible worlds. Furthermore, the
claim both Socrates and Euthyphro agree on as an answer to the Euthyphro Dilemma, i.e. the thesis (EG)
that concerns the ontological priority between God's love and goodness and
includes a commitment to moral realism rather than moral anti-realism, is very
arguable as well. For instance, if God's judgment of a thing's moral status was
the cause of that status rather than its effect, the root of morality would
seem to boil down, someone might argue, to a sheer caprice or whim of a divine agent.
Furthermore, as a result, moral standards would appear nothing but wholly
arbitrary. Again, someone could find it hard to think highly of the goodness of
God himself, for an agent who managed to live up to a self-made standard would
not strike us as a particularly admirable being.
I am not claiming that the thesis
(EG) is unproblematic. One might, of course, argue for the opposite. For
instance, one might perhaps point out that the judgments of an omnipotent God
cannot be regulated by moral standards that exist prior to those judgments. One
might also consider God's unlimited freedom and independence as grounds for the
view that a thing's moral status is dependent upon God's judgment rather than
the other way around. What I am claiming, however, is that there is ample room
for such moral semantics, epistemology, and ontology that enable one to accept
the argument against Euthyphro without being committed to the claim that the
equivalence (EE) is trivially true.
6. Euthyphro and the Open Question
Two important purportedly necessary
equivalences have been discussed in this paper:
(EE) For all x, x is good if an only if x is loved by God;
(EM) For all x, x is good if and only if x is N.
The
argument against Euthyphro aims to show that (EE) is not conceptually
necessary, whereas Moore's open-question argument purports to draw the same conclusion
for (EM). These arguments can be read to bear structural similarity, but, I
have argued, there is a crucial difference: Moore's open-question argument is
acceptable only if (EM) is trivially true, whereas the argument against
Euthyphro can be accepted without being committed to the view that (EE) is
trivially true. Hence, the paradox of analysis is an issue for Moore's argument
in a way that it is not for the proponent of the argument against Euthyphro.
One may, then, well be sympathetic to the latter argument without being at all
convinced that the open-question argument is plausible.[6]
REFERENCES
Boyd, R. 1988. How To Be a
Moral Realist. In Essays on Moral Realism,
ed. G. Sayre-McCord, 181-228. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Fumerton, R. 1983. The Paradox
of Analysis. Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research 43: 477-497.
Horgan, T and M. Timmons.
1992. Troubles for New Wave Moral Semantics: The 'Open Question Argument'
Revived. Philosophical Papers 21:
153-175.
Johnston, M. 1993. Objectivity
Refigured: Pragmatism without Verificationism. In Reality, Representation & Projection, ed. J. Haldane and C.
Wright, 85-130.
Kripke, S. 1972. Naming and Necessity. In Semantics of Natural Language, ed. G.
Harman and D. Davidson, 253-355. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Langford, C. H. 1942. The
Notion of Analysis in Moore's Philosophy. In The Philosophy of G. E. Moore, ed. P. A. Schilpp, 321-342. La
Salle, Illinois: Open Court.
Miller, A. 1995. Objectivity
Disfigured: Mark Johnston's Missing-Explanation Argument. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60: 857-868.
Miller, A. 2004. An Introduction to Contemporary Metaethics.
Cambridge: Polity Press.
Moore, G. E. 1954 [1903]. Principia Ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Moore, G. E. 1942. A Reply to
My Critics, §11: Analysis. In The
Philosophy of G. E. Moore, ed. P. A. Schilpp, 660-667. La Salle, Illinois:
Open Court.
Moore, G. E. 1991. Elements of Ethics, ed. T. Regan.
Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Plato 1997. Euthyphro. In Plato: Complete Works, ed. J. M. Cooper. Indianapolis: Hackett.
Putnam, H. 1975. The Meaning
of "Meaning". In his Mind,
Language, and Reality. Philosophical
Papers, vol. 2, 215-271. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Sharvy, R. 1972. Euthyphro
9d-11b: Analysis and Definition in Plato and Others. Noûs 6:119-137.
Sayre-McCord, J. 1997. 'Good'
on Twin Earth. Philosophical Issues
8: 267-292.
Regan, T. 1991. Editor's
Introduction. In Elements of Ethics, ed.
T. Regan. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Notes
[1] Notice that Miller is not the only one who is
aware of the similarities between Moore's and Socrates’ arguments. Richard
Sharvy (1972), for one, discusses these similarities.
[2] It should be noted that this is not the only
possible solution to our question. For instance, Richard Sharvy argues that,
despite some superficial similarities between Moore’s argument and Socrates’
argument, these similarities disappear when Socrates’ argument is viewed as
essentially involving principles about formal causation rather than principles
about substitution (see Sharvy 1972).
[3] The ‘because’ of explanation is to be
distinguished from the ‘because’ of conceptual articulation. According to the
present distinction, for instance, the statement “John is a bachelor because he
is an unmarried male of marriageable age” is a conceptual articulation of
John’s bachelorhood (see Miller 1995, 858), whereas the statement “John is a
bachelor because he prefers to be single” (at least potentially) explains why
John is a bachelor.
[4] Incidentally, Moore (1942, 661) continued to
insist that analysandum and analysans the same concepts even after
Langford (1942, 322-323) had set forth the paradox of analysis to him. As a
reaction to Langford’s criticism, Moore (1942, 666) stated that, in a correct
conceptual analysis, analysandum and analysans are different expressions of
the same concept. It is not easy to see how the paradox of analysis could be
avoided this way, and Moore (ibid.) in fact admitted that he has no clear
solution to the paradox.
[5] The semantic advances due to Kripke and Putnam
have motivated some philosophers to develop the so-called new wave moral
realism in which moral terms behave, pretty much at least, like natural kind
terms. For instance, according to the naturalistic moral realism of Richard
Boyd (see his 1988), moral terms rigidly designate natural properties that
causally regulate the correct use of these terms, without there being any
synonymy between moral terms and naturalistic terms (see also Horgan &
Timmons 1992, 159 for a terse summary of Boyd’s moral semantics). Jeffrey
Sayre-McCord, for one, has defended a meta-ethical rigid designation theory
without any ineradicable naturalistic strand. In Sayre-McCord’s thinking, moral
terms resist analytic definitions but rigidly designate moral kinds that
causally regulate the correct use of moral terms; furthermore, according to
Sayre-McCord, it is irrelevant whether moral kinds coincide with natural kinds
(Sayre-McCord 1997, 269-270, 285). The view I am attributing to the proponent
of the argument against Euthyphro differs in an important sense from both
naturalistic and non-naturalistic new wave moral realism, though. To wit, new
wave moral realism includes the idea that the property of being good is identical with some purported property
P, without there being any synonymy between the terms that refer to good and P,
respectively. This does not hold good for the view I am here attributing to the
proponent of the argument against Euthyphro; she does not claim that the
properties being good and being loved by God are identical.
[6] I would like to thank a referee of Minerva for
helpful comments. My work on this paper has been financially supported by the
Academy of Finland (grant 8114178).
Copyright © 2009 Minerva
All rights
are reserved, but fair and good faith use with full attribution may be made of
this work for educational or scholarly purposes.
Dr. Timo
Kajamies is a post-doctoral researcher at the department of Philosophy,
University of Turku, Finland.
Return to Minerva (Volume 13) Main Page
Go to Top of This Page