ISSN 1393-614X Minerva - An Internet Journal of
Philosophy Vol. 9 2005.
____________________________________________________
Truthmaking and Pragmatist Conceptions of Truth and
Reality Sami Pihlström |
Abstract
This paper argues for a rearticulation of the theory of truthmaking
within pragmatism. The concept of truthmaking has usually been employed by
metaphysical realists (such as D.M. Armstrong), but it can be reinterpreted in
a pragmatist manner, following both classical and more recent pragmatists’
(e.g., William James’s and Hilary Putnam’s) ideas on the “making of truth” (or
“worldmaking”) as a process within human experience and world-categorization.
Thus, a pragmatist criticism of metaphysical realism can be extended to the
core areas of realist metaphysics, including the truthmaking theory.
1.
Introduction
The concept of truthmaking is
usually associated with metaphysical projects of a distinctively realist flavor. The truthmaking theorist
typically strives to identify those elements of the world – that is, the real,
mind- and language-independent world – that make our propositions (insofar as
they are true) true. The truthmaking theory is thus also sometimes regarded as
a way of explicating the correspondence
theory of truth – an explication of that age-old theory more metaphysical
than, e.g., Alfred Tarski’s influential semantic conception of truth. Insofar
as the correspondence theory of truth and the idea of the world itself as
something that makes our truths true are elements of what has been called metaphysical realism, it might even be
claimed that the truthmaking theory is essentially committed to metaphysical
realism. Such an impression is strengthened, if one takes a look at influential
strongly realist formulations of the notion of truthmaking, such as David
Armstrong’s (1997, 2004). Armstrong, obviously, should be taken to be committed
to metaphysical realism, roughly in Hilary Putnam’s (1981, 1990) well-known
sense (see Pihlström 2006b).
In this essay, I shall examine whether the notion of truthmaking might,
however, have a role to play in somewhat less strongly realist views,
especially in pragmatism or (what
some authors call) pragmatic realism
(see, e.g., Putnam 1990; Pihlström 1996, 2003; and several essays in Shook
2003). This suggestion is not as odd as it may first seem. There are
metaphysicians who think that the truthmaking theory, as such, is
metaphysically neutral. For example, Johanna Seibt (2000) draws a sharp
distinction between ontology and metaphysics: ontology, for her, is a
theory of truthmakers and remains neutral with respect to the realism vs.
idealism debate, because different (e.g., realist or idealist) interpretations
of the postulated truthmakers (i.e., the ontological categories the theorist
commits her/himself to) are possible. These interpretations are, then, “metaphysical
valuations” of the structure(s) of the truthmakers one is ontologically
committed to.
My purpose is not to endorse Seibt’s position as such, or to elaborate
on the specific truthmakers she postulates, but to use her idea of the
metaphysical neutrality of truthmaking theory as a starting-point for an
investigation of the way(s) in which pragmatism might, especially in its
“pragmatically realist” versions, accommodate some plausible insights of the
truthmaking theory. I shall begin, however, by explicating, in broad strokes, a
metaphysically realist version of the theory, viz., Armstrong’s. My ideas
concerning the relations between truthmaking and pragmatist views on truth and
reality will emerge against that background. I make no claims to covering the
recently lively truthmaking discussion with any historical accuracy. There are
plenty of rival theories available – for example, in addition to Armstrong’s
writings, the pioneering work by Kevin Mulligan and his collaborators (1984).
(See also the papers collected in Lillehammer & Rodriguez-Pereyra 2003.)
2.
Armstrong’s theory of truthmaking
The most comprehensive source for Armstrong’s sophisticated theory is
his recent book, Truth and Truthmakers
(2004), although the concept of truthmaking was already centrally employed in a
previous work by him, A World of States
of Affairs (1997). The more recent book argues for the general
philosophical relevance of the concept of truthmaking, for a particular
conception of what the truthmaking relation is (including two key theses,
“truthmaker necessitarianism” and “truthmaker maximalism”), as well as for a
number of carefully laid-out views about what kinds of truthmakers we need in
various areas of metaphysical theorizing (e.g., in our treatment of things and their
properties, of modalities, of numbers and other abstract objects, and of
natural laws).[1]
First, we should note that the term “making” is not used in a causal
sense in the theory of truthmaking – either Armstrong’s or anyone else’s.
Rather, Armstrong’s (2004) use of this expression intends to capture the idea
that there is something in the world – “some existent, some portion of reality,
in virtue of which” a given truth is
true (p. 5; emphasis added). Armstrong regards propositions as the (primary)
truthbearers (see ibid., pp. 12-16). It is not necessary to dwell on the issue
of truthbearers here. Armstrong, as a naturalist and materialist, wishes to
provide a fully naturalist, this-worldly account of propositions, treating them
as possible intentional objects (and analyzing possibilities combinatorially,
thus avoiding the postulation of real possible worlds), but of course we need
not stick to his analysis. Pragmatists speak more variously about truthbearers.
As we shall see, for William James, truths are primarily true beliefs or true
“ideas” (whatever that ultimately means); yet, I have nothing against
Armstrong’s and many others’ way of speaking about propositions as the content
of such beliefs or ideas, provided that an inflationary ontology of propositions
as necessarily existing abstract entities is avoided. More recent pragmatists,
such as Richard Rorty, have typically regarded linguistic entities (e.g.,
sentences) as those things that can be said to be true or false. (See also
Kirkham 1992.)
Allowing Armstrong’s commitment to propositions, the truthmaking
relation, for him, is a relation obtaining between a true proposition and the
“portion of reality” in virtue of which it is true, or which makes the
proposition true. This relation is a “cross-categorial” one, because it holds
between entities belonging to different ontological categories, i.e., between a
proposition and the entity or entities that make(s) it true (Armstrong 2004, p.
5). Furthermore, truthmaking is an “internal” relation in the sense that “given
just the terms of the relation, the relation between them is necessitated”
(ibid., p. 9). Such a relation is “no addition of being”, nothing over and
above the terms themselves (i.e., in this case, the proposition which is true
and the truthmaker that makes it true), although this, according to Armstrong,
is not to say that the relation does not exist.
It is somewhat puzzling, however, that Armstrong (ibid., p. 37) also
calls the “truth/truthmaking relation” a “semantic” one. It would be more
natural for him to say (as he at least implicitly seems to maintain) that truth
is a semantic notion while truthmaking is its metaphysical ground. In his
introduction to a volume of essays on realism and antirealism, William Alston
(2002, p. 4) explains this idea by saying that “the issue over the nature of
truth is logically independent of the metaphysics of facts, of truth makers” –
even though a realist metaphysics of facts is the natural choice for someone
who holds a realist conception of truth (the “alethic realist”; cf. Alston
1996). While Alston thinks that alethic and metaphysical realisms are
independent, René van Woudenberg (2002) argues in the same volume that a
realist conception of truth involves metaphysical commitments, in general to mind-independent
facts as truthmakers, and more particularly to the existence of a
mind-independent, non-relational, and non-dispositional property of being true.
(Such a property might be invoked as the truthmaker of the truth of alethic
realism, if such a position is true.)
Among Armstrong’s more controversial theses, truthmaker necessitarianism declares that the truthmaking relation
is a necessitating relation: the truthmaker necessitates the truth which is
true in virtue of it. If the truthmaker exists, then the corresponding truth
cannot fail to be true. Of course, necessitation in this metaphysical sense
must be carefully distinguished from necessary truth; the truthmaker of a
contingent truth exists only contingently, but if it does exist, then that truth must be true. Furthermore, this
necessitation of a truth by its truthmaker, because of the cross-categorial
nature of the relation, is not to be misconstrued as logical entailment, which
could obtain only between propositions (Armstrong 2004, pp. 5-6).
Another central thesis is truthmaker
maximalism, according to which every truth has a truthmaker. Armstrong
admits that he does not have any direct argument for maximalism, but hopes that
“philosophers of realist inclinations will be immediately attracted to the idea
that a truth, any truth, should depend for its truth for something ‘outside’
it, in virtue of which it is true” (ibid., p. 7).[2] He does show in great detail how (in his view) plausible truthmakers
can be found for truths about various different things in different ontological
categories.
Armstrong defends, and relies on, yet another meta-level or
methodological thesis, the entailment
principle, which says that if a truthmaker makes a certain proposition
true, and if that proposition entails another proposition, then the same
truthmaker also makes the entailed proposition true (ibid., pp. 10 ff.). This
principle plays a key methodological role in Armstrong’s argumentation, but we
need not pay further attention to it here. Another central concept that we can
bracket here is the concept of a minimal
truthmaker – a truthmaker for a proposition such that nothing can be subtracted
from the truthmaker in such a way that it would still serve as a truthmaker for
that proposition (ibid., p. 20). For ontologically parsimonious truthmaker
theorists, the search for a minimal truthmaker of a truth is, understandably,
an extremely important task.
On the grounds of his truthmaker theory, presented here only in a barest
outline, Armstrong arrives at what he declares to be a realist theory of truth: “p
(a proposition) is true if and only if there exists a T (some entity in the
world) such that T necessitates that p
and p is true in virtue of T” (ibid.,
p. 17). In the earlier book, Armstrong (1997, p. 128) noted that while the
semantics of the truth predicate might be accounted for in terms of a
redundancy theory, the correspondence theory must be accepted on a “deeper, ontological
level”, that is, as the requirement of providing truthmakers for truths. The
realist definition Armstrong gives is not an explicit definition (because, as
such, it would be circular), but it is obviously designed to capture the
intuitions of realist correspondence theorists who hold that truths must
correspond to the way the world is. I think it clearly very well succeeds in
this task. The correspondence relation, as such, is often thought to be vacuous
or metaphysically mysterious. The truthmaking relation explicates what this
relation comes down to, at least for the metaphysical realist who believes that
we can make sense of the metaphysical relation of necessitation. Truths should
not only correspond to the world, but it should be the world itself – the
entities that really exist – that makes those truths true, or that plays the
role of something in virtue of which they are true. The direction of
determination goes from the largely mind-independent world (the entities there
really are) to the truths about it (propositions).[3]
3.
Pragmatists on truthmaking (and
worldmaking)
Turning now to pragmatism, we of course find metaphysical (and
anti-metaphysical) views very different from Armstrong’s, who, after all, pays
almost no attention at all to pragmatism – not even by criticizing it. Yet, the
notion of truthmaking, in some sense at least, can be perceived to be at work
in, or at least read into, a number of key pragmatist texts.
In particular, William James (1907, 1909a) famously argued for a dynamic
conception of truth according to which truths are “made” rather than found (for
more detailed discussions, see Pihlström 1996, 1998, 2004b). More precisely,
truths are made in the course of human experience. Truth “happens to an idea” (James 1907, p. 97), instead of being a
timeless, abstract, unchanging relation eternally obtaining between a true idea
and something that exists independently of it (and which the truth, according
to the most naive versions of realism, would simply “copy”). Thus, ideas or beliefs
(or other truthbearers) are not eternally true but “become true just in so far as they help us to get into satisfactory
relation with other parts of our experience” (ibid., p. 34). “Truth is made, just as health, wealth and strength are made, in the course
of experience” (ibid., p. 104). Even the regulative notion of “absolute truth”
designates something that “will have to be made,
made as a relation incidental to the growth of a mass of
verification-experience, to which the half-true ideas are all along
contributing their quota” (ibid., p. 107).
In passages like this, the notion of truthmaking is at least
metaphorically employed – though of course within an overall philosophical
position very different from Armstrong’s metaphysical realism. James, seeking
the “cash-value” of truths “in experiential terms” (see ibid., p. 97), has
little patience with the realist view, held in James’s time by Bertrand
Russell, among others, that truths simply correspond to or are made true by
objects or states of affairs that exist ontologically independently of those
truths. Instead, the making of truths in and through experience also amounts to
the making of reality: the world – as experienced and understood by us humans –
is a human construction, at least up to a point (cf. Pihlström 1996, ch. 3;
1998, ch. 1). The direction of determination is not, or not merely, from the
world to the true beliefs that are about it; human subjects of (true) belief,
with their pragmatic needs and habits of action, partly determine what the
world is like. This view was developed in a more radical manner by James’s
younger pragmatist contemporary F.C.S. Schiller, whose 1907 collection, Studies in Humanism, contains essays
with titles such as “The Making of Truth” and “The Making of Reality” (for some
comparisons between James and Schiller, see again Pihlström 1998, ch. 1).
Let us – turning from the concept of truth to the other pole of the
truthmaking relation, the concept of reality (or the world) – take a look at a
few other key passages in which James and later pragmatists employ the concept
of “making”. In his late work, A
Pluralistic Universe (1909b, pp. 117-118), James claims, with Henri
Bergson, that “[w]hat really exists
is not things made but things in the making” and talks about “put[ting]
yourself in the making” of things “by
a stroke of intuitive sympathy” (emphases in the original). In this sense,
reality is something we (help to) create, to which we always inevitably make an
“addition” – in a word, something “still in the making” (James 1907, pp.
121-123). Anything we may call a thing
is “carved out” by us (ibid., p. 122). According to Schiller, again, the
“pragmatically real world”, far from being a ready-made, “original datum” of
experience, is “an elaborate construction, made by us, individually and
socially, by a purposive selection of the more efficacious, and a rejection of
the less efficacious portions of a ‘primary reality’” (Schiller 1907, p. 460).
Schiller argued, in a manner close to James’s, that as knowers of reality we
inevitably alter, and thus contribute to the making of, reality. The unmade
“primary reality” is, as such, nothing for us, but it is turned into a
pragmatically meaningful, humanly significant reality possessing a certain
structure (only) through the “humanist” process of “making”. (Cf. Schiller
1907, pp. 13, 186-187, 198-202, 216-223, 425-426, 433, 439, 444, 474.)
Here, of course, the relevant “making” relation is not the Armstrongian
realist truthmaking relation obtaining between a true proposition and the
independent piece of reality which necessitates its truth. Yet, the “making” of
reality that James and Schiller talk about seems to be something that the
“world” itself does, too, at least insofar as we, as knowers of reality, are
ourselves parts of the world or reality that we help to structure. Truth- or
worldmaking would not be possible without our contribution to the way(s) the
world is, but we are undeniably parts of the world as well. The world can thus
be said to make truths true, but only through us, for whom there is a world (or truth) in the first place. There is,
as Schiller puts it, a primary reality independently of us, but that reality makes nothing true; it is a
mere abstraction of thought, or, in James’s words, something “absolutely dumb and
evanescent, the merely ideal limit of our minds” (James 1907, p. 119). Even so,
James did not deny the existence of a “standing reality independent of the idea
that knows it” (James 1909a, p. 88). Clearly, he wanted to save the minimal
rational core of realism (and the correspondence theory), while defending a
picture of truth richer and pragmatically more nuanced than the one he found in
his realist rivals’ theories.
From these pragmatists’ point of view, one might in any case argue that
if Armstrongian metaphysicians regard that kind of a metaphysically primary
reality as the source of truthmakers, they erroneously claim something about a
reality which has, and can have, no structure (for us) at all. Any structured
reality – any reality whose entities could make anything true – must, according
to pragmatism, be a humanly categorized reality. All categorization, moreover,
arises as a response to specific needs (to be further analyzed along pragmatist
lines); accordingly, if the world or reality is to make any truths true, it
must already have been “made” (and must be continuously remade) by us
world-categorizing concept-users whose categorizing activities are themselves
constrained by and oriented toward certain human needs, goals, interests, or
purposes. The world which makes our human truths true is itself continuously
“in the making”. It is, to use Deweyan rather than Jamesian terms, a reality
with a “practical character”.
This kind of experiential and practice-embedded making of truths (and
indeed of the world itself) was not emphasized by the father of pragmatism,
Charles S. Peirce, who on the whole defended views much more realistic than
either James or the other pragmatists of those days (cf. Pihlström 2003, ch.
3). Something similar was, however, emphasized by John Dewey, who even wanted
to replace the traditional talk about truth with talk about “warranted
assertibility” – something that is certainly dependent on our human points of
view to the world. Later pragmatists, including Hilary Putnam and Nelson
Goodman (among whom the latter never wanted to describe his views as
pragmatist, though), have more explicitly revived the idea of truthmaking, or
(in Goodman’s case, more radically) worldmaking.
Truths and the world (or, in Goodman’s pluralist and relativist theory, worlds) they are true about are,
according to these neopragmatists, human constructions, “made” by us in the
course of our experiential and symbolic ways of representing and acting.
Goodman, in particular, is explicit about the metaphor of making – or
perhaps it is not even correct to refer to it as a “metaphor” at all. He claims
to move from “a world fixed and found”, with its unique truths, to a diversity
of right, even conflicting, world-versions
and “worlds in the making” (Goodman 1978, p. x). We make worlds by making right
versions through our various symbol systems. Truth itself is world- or
version-relative: different worlds, different truths. Note that this is not to say that the world, or the
particular version of the world at issue, does not make true the truths that
hold in that world. But note also that this discussion of the plurality of
worlds must, as Goodman explicitly urges, be distinguished from the debates
over the plurality of possible worlds (cf., e.g., Lewis 1986): the worlds or
versions we make are actual. Yet, our making of worlds or truths is not a
creation ex nihilo: making is
“remaking” (Goodman 1978, pp. 6-7). But the crucial point is that this is
making nonetheless, even in cases in which it seems that we simply “find” what
is “out there”, e.g., the stars, which seem to be paradigmatic examples of
objects existing independently of our beliefs, perceptions, language-use,
theories, or symbol systems. “We have to make what we find, be it the Great
Dipper, Sirius, food, fuel, or a stereo system.” (Goodman 1984, p. 36.) As we
just saw James expressing these ideas, we must “carve out” whatever we conceive
of as an object, or a thing of any kind, even the stars. We are, among other
things, “starmakers” (cf. also James 1907, p. 121; McCormick 1996).
While bringing up, particularly in his later writings, some reservations
about Goodman’s theory going too far in the direction of antirealism or
“irrealism” (Goodman’s own term), sacrificing the empirical reality of objects
such as stars (cf. Putnam 1992), Putnam – in an earlier incarnation – also
joins in here by claiming that “‘objects’ themselves are as much made as
discovered, as much products of our conceptual intervention as of the
‘objective’ factor in experience” (Putnam 1981, p. 54). The reality we live in
and about which our statements can be true is a reality with a “human face”
(Putnam 1990). Putnam’s more recent writings (e.g., his 1994, 1999) are filled
by defenses of commonsense realism and, along with it, the notion of the
independence of worldly objects, but he has not given up the pragmatism which
already to some extent gave flavor to his (now rejected or at least heavily
reinterpreted) internal realism (see also Pihlström 1996, 1998, 2004a).
Several realist critics still read Putnam as an antirealist (cf., e.g.,
a number of essays in Alston 2002). This can hardly be correct, given Putnam’s
recent rethinking of his views on realism. In fact, Putnam has occasionally
revived a surprisingly realist-sounding concept of truthmaking (without
explicating it in any analytic detail, though), to which we will return in a
moment. Although Putnam rarely uses this term, we might read his continuing
criticisms of minimalist and disquotational theories of truth, including theories
preferring assertibility conditions to truth conditions, as attacks on the
tendency of these theories to give up what is sound in the notion of
truthmaking (see Putnam 1994, 1995, 1999). Thus, Putnam wants to save the
realist conviction that something non-linguistic is needed to account for the
truths we are able to formulate in our languages. Given his insistence on the
need to invoke something like the truthmaking relation, there is a distinction
to be drawn between those pragmatists who find the concept of truthmaking
important (in a way or another, though presumably never in Armstrong’s strongly
realist way) and those who do not. The former camp includes both Goodman (if we
incline to think that worldmaking is a kind of truthmaking) and Putnam, while
the latter one includes, arguably, philosophers like Richard Rorty and Donald
Davidson (whom Rorty notoriously claims to be a pragmatist of sorts). However,
if we interpret Davidson’s (1984, p. 194) statement that nothing in the world
“makes” our sentences true simply as a denial of the metaphysically-realist
idea that some fixed objects or properties in the non-linguistic world in
itself make our true sentences (or propositions) true, or stand in one-to-one
correspondence to them, then it is as plausible as the general rejection of
metaphysically-realist construals of truthmaking and the correspondence theory
of truth is, according to Jamesian or Putnamian pragmatists. Note that
Davidson, as a disciple of Quine, speaks about the truth of sentences rather than
propositions. Again, I make no claims about what the true truthbearers are. In
any case, Davidson (1990, especially pp. 303-304) is very critical of the
correspondence theory (see also, however, Niiniluoto 2004, p. 58).
However, if these claims by Davidson (and Rorty) are interpreted in a
way which makes pragmatic realism itself seem suspect, they are more vulnerable
to Jamesian or Putnamian pragmatist criticism. If there is no relation at all between our sentences or propositions and the
world they are supposed to be about (and about which they are, in lucky cases,
true), then little remains from even the mildest form of pragmatic realism.
Something like truthmaking is needed in any pragmatic realism worth the name,
unless one wants to go all the way toward Rortyan antirepresentationalism – a
view which most pragmatism scholars regard as an extremely controversial
construal of what is essential in pragmatism (cf. Pihlström 1996, 1998).
As already indicated,
Putnam, while occasionally speaking metaphorically about “the mind and the
world jointly mak[ing] up the mind and the world” (Putnam 1981, p. xi),
actually embraces the idea of truthmaking, at least in his relatively recent
writings. It is also worth noting that, as he points out, a version of this
idea is actually present in Davidson’s seminal 1974 paper attacking conceptual
relativism:
[…] in the very last sentence of [“On the Very Idea of
a Conceptual Scheme”, p. 198] Davidson speaks of “the familiar objects whose antics
make our sentences and opinions true or false.” This remark would seem to
suggest that Davidson doesn’t mean to deny that objects, be they near or be
they distant from us in space and time, sometimes make our sentences true. (If he had, I should now be quarreling
with Davidson, as well as with Rorty.) Rather, Davidson’s point seems to be
that we must not think that true sentences correspond one by one to special
objects which “make them true,” call them “states of affairs” […]. (Putnam
1994, p. 300; emphasis in the original.)
That is, Putnam should be
quarreling with Davidson, had
Davidson denied the notion of truthmaking altogether – which, Putnam seems to
be saying, he never did (as should be evident to anyone who
has read the final sentence of Davidson’s paper). Although Putnam goes on to
say that he disagrees with Davidson on the claim that it is “verboten to speak of ‘states of affairs’
at all” (ibid., p. 301), because the category of states of affairs is among the
ontological categories we may legitimately use (with some definite pragmatic
purposes in mind) within our various ontological structurings of reality, we
can perceive here a profound affinity between these two thinkers’ views. The
real opposition is, rather, to be found between Putnam and Rorty (including
Rorty’s employment of allegedly Davidsonian ideas), because Rorty, unlike
Putnam, rejects the very idea of things or the world (or anything, for that
matter) making truths true (see ibid., p. 300). Unfortunately, we must leave
the details of the Putnam–Rorty comparison aside here (cf. Pihlström 2004a). In
a word, for Rorty, there are only causal – flatly physical – relations between
language and the world, no semantic or representational (let alone
metaphysical) ones. In any event, pace
Rorty and Davidson, the pragmatically acceptable idea of truthmaking should be
carefully distinguished from the naive view that our sentences or propositions
correspond “one-by-one” to objects or states of affairs in the world. Neither
metaphysically realist truthmaking theorists like Armstrong, nor their
pragmatist rivals, should accept such a notion of correspondence.
In criticizing Rorty and Davidson, Putnam comes surprisingly close to
the kind of view Armstrong holds. (Similar commitments to facts or states of
affairs as truthmakers can be found, for instance, in Putnam’s 1994 Dewey
Lectures, reprinted in Putnam 1999.) However, I think it is clear that Putnam
would never join Armstrong in claiming that the world an sich consists of states of affairs or that it could be described
as consisting of states of affairs from a privileged (“absolute”, “God’s-Eye”)
perspective. Furthermore, Putnam’s qualified agreement with Davidson by no
means entails that he would find Davidson’s criticism of conceptual relativism
appealing; on the contrary, he has repeatedly defended what he calls conceptual
relativity, as well as the doctrine
of pluralism partly adopted from the
classical pragmatists (cf. Putnam 1990, 1999, 2004; for several recent critical
discussions of these ideas, see the essays in Alston 2002; see also Pihlström
2006a). In his treatment of Davidson just cited, Putnam (1994, p. 301) goes on
to remind us that we should not ask “whether states of affairs ‘really exist’
or not” (this, apparently, would commit us to metaphysical realism) but
“whether notions like ‘state of affairs’ are to be conceived of as having a
single determinate meaning or whether they are more happily conceived in terms
of an open and ever extendable family of uses”. Putnam’s conceptual relativity
would, obviously, suggest the latter. These issues cannot be settled here,
though. Among Putnam’s critics, Niiniluoto (2004, p. 70) claims that a realist
committed to THE WORLD (“in itself”, as it were) can accept “conceptual
pluralism”, but a Putnamian pragmatist or pluralist can hardly find this
attempted via media plausible (for
more details, see Pihlström 1996, 1998).
Putnam’s views on truthmakers extend to his criticism of not only
Davidson and Rorty but of Quine’s “immanent” conception of truth (as something
within language) as well:
In
my view, whatever authority [ontology or epistemology] had depended entirely on
our conceiving of reality and sensations as, respectively, the makers-true and
the makers-justified of the sentences we produce – not the makers-true and the
makers-justified from within the story, but the things outside the story that
hook language onto something outside itself. If Quine is right, then Rorty is
right. If the makers-true and the makers-justified have really turned out to be
“immanent,” then they have also become “optional.” Quine’s talk of what is
“first-class” and what is “second-class” becomes mere rhetoric. (Putnam 1994,
p. 348.)
Putnam here clearly implies that, in his view, ontology is, or has
traditionally been conceived as, a matter of providing “makers-true” for true
sentences – truthmakers that are to be found, in typical cases at least,
outside language and not merely (immanently) “within the story”, whether
scientific (à la Quine) or
non-scientific (à la Rorty). He does
not explicitly commit himself to such a project of ontology; on the contrary,
his more recent work constitutes a devastating critique of the very idea of
ontology (see Putnam 2004; Pihlström 2006a). But he does distance himself from
the Quinean-Rortyan attempt to turn ontologizing merely immanent.
Among recent pragmatists, then, Putnam can, with some qualifications, be
reinterpreted as a truthmaker theorist of some sort, and it would be
interesting to see his explicit reactions to the theory that Armstrong has put
forward. On the other hand, Armstrong’s specific views will undoubtedly strike
Putnam as too heavily metaphysically realist. A fruitful reinterpretation of
those views in terms of pragmatism would be needed to make them fit Putnam’s
looser, somewhat metaphorical notion of truthmaking. In attempting such a
reinterpretation, we may creatively employ the views of earlier pragmatists
like James, Schiller, and Goodman, for whom the metaphor of making is,
arguably, more central than it is for Putnam but who are, from the perspective
of pragmatic realism, frequently led to unacceptably antirealist
(constructivist) ontologies.
4.
Metaphysically realist truthmaking
versus pragmatically realist truthmaking
We have seen how pragmatists can
(though of course need not) employ a
concept of truthmaking (perhaps in several variations), although such a concept
is, in pragmatist theories, usually employed within an overall metaphysics very
different from the metaphysical realist’s one – a more processual, dynamic,
practice-embedded metaphysics that refuses to draw any principled dichotomies
between the world as it is in itself and the world as it is experienced by
humans engaging in their unending diversity of practices and habits of action.
Such a metaphysics can still be realist, though only pragmatically realist,
insofar as it does not reject the claim that there is something “out there”
that we never made up out of nothing. Pragmatists, emphasizing our need to
struggle with the concrete facts of worldly existence, should be the first to
note that truthmaking is not, naively, a “making up” of truths. We live in a
concrete, natural world, shaping the world through our experiences, and it is
this very world, to some extent shaped by us but irreducible to our contingent
and changing structurings of it, that makes true whatever we claim to be true,
insofar as our claims to truth are (pragmatically) justified or “right”.
Goodman (1978, 1984), among others, finds rightness
a more fundamental concept than truth. More generally, pragmatists from James
onwards have conceptualized truth as a species of the good, thus linking
epistemic and ethical considerations (see also Pihlström 2005).
We should now perceive, further, that pragmatism is not only entitled to
the vocabulary of truthmaking but can accommodate much of what Armstrong (2004)
says, including the ontological commitments to universals (consider Peirce’s
defense of the reality of “generals”) and states of affairs – though only in a
reinterpreted sense. These are commitments to the need (a deeply human need) to
postulate certain categories within a humanly categorized reality, a world
which receives an ontological structure through human practice-embedded
categorization (cf. Pihlström 1996, 1998, 2003, 2006a). What we cannot accept,
however, is Armstrong’s Russellian views about the need to postulate “totality
states of affairs” – except for local totalities or wholes that are never meant
to cover the totality of the world as such. There is no “totality” of the world
itself, because such a totality is, very simply, never pragmatically
structurable or categorizable by us humans. Kant (1781/1787), in his famous
Antinomies, attacked precisely the rationalist metaphysicians’ claims to know
something about the world as conceived as a totality, e.g., whether the world
has spatio-temporal boundaries or not. Putnam’s rejection of “a definite
Totality of All Real Objects” (see, e.g., Putnam 1994, p. 303) is equally firm.
At best, we may speak about the world as a totality or as a whole as an
abstraction, not very different from Kant’s “thing in itself”, that we may
pragmatically need as a reminder of the fallibility of our knowledge claims,
which are always inevitably presented from local human perspectives.
Armstrong himself (see his 2004, chs. 5-6) believes that totality states
of affairs or “general facts” are needed as truthmakers for negative and general truths (among which
the latter are a special case of the former). This postulation is motivated, or
even required, by his truthmaker necessitarianism. If the world is a contingent
totality of states of affairs (let us grant this to Armstrong for the sake of
argument), then it seems to be clear that this contingent totality, all by
itself, is not sufficient as the truthmaker of the truth that these and only
these states of affairs constitute the world. It does not necessitate the
truth. This is precisely because the world, as contingent, might have been “smaller” or “bigger”. What is needed in addition to
the first-order states of affairs themselves is the totality state of affairs
of those states of affairs’ being all the states of affairs there are, a
general fact that “collects” them (cf. ibid., p. 59). Among such general facts,
which may be more or less local and restricted (e.g., the truthmaker for the
truth about there being a definite totality of chairs in this room), there is
“a huge general fact (state of affairs) that is the most general state of
affairs of all” (ibid.). This “biggest totality state of all, the one embracing
all lower-order states of affairs”, is all that is needed to provide
truthmakers for lesser totality truths and negative truths (ibid., p. 75; see
also Armstrong’s earlier treatment of totality states of affairs in his 1997).
Now, while truthmaker-based metaphysical theories about universals,
states of affairs, or even about the way in which possibilities can be
constructed out of recombinations of the elements of the actual world (cf. also
Armstrong 1997), can be rearticulated in a pragmatist setting, always making it
explicit that we are talking about an empirical world whose ontological
structuring is not ready-made or given in advance but results from a human
practice-embedded categorization, the metaphysics of “allness”, or totality,
that Armstrong (2004, ch. 6) is committed to through his account of the
truthmakers for negative and general truths cannot be thus rearticulated (or so
it seems to me).[4] This metaphysics more directly presupposes not only that it makes sense
to speak about the ontological structure of the world as it is in itself but
also that there is such a thing as
the world as it is in itself, as the given contingent totality it is. This idea
contrasts with the Jamesian-Schillerian-Goodmanesque view of the world(s) being
constantly “in the making”. According to these pragmatists (and even according
to their somewhat more realistically inclined followers, such as Putnam), there
is no such thing as the totality of the world, as “ready-made”; moreover, the
problem is not just that there, contingently, is no such thing but that we do
not know what we are talking about when we make claims about there being such a
thing. Our claims to know, or even meaningfully state, something about the
totality of the world, about all the objects there are, or about all the states
of affairs that obtain, have only the illusion of sense, if we take seriously
the pragmatists’ emphasis on the world’s being in the making in and through
human experience. This issue would require more detailed attention, but we may
here safely rely on Putnam’s (1981, 1990, 1994, 2004) arguments for conceptual
relativity (for further discussion and engagement with secondary literature,
see again Pihlström 1996, 1998, 2003, 2006a; and Alston 2002).
The pragmatist, I have argued, has a right to the truthmaking vocabulary
and even to some specific doctrines one may arrive at through truthmaking
considerations (though only in a heavily reinterpreted sense). It is important
to distinguish truthmaking from metaphysical realism, thus saving this useful
metaphysical concept from scientistic metaphysical realisms like Armstrong’s.
Such realists urge that we do not in
any sense “make” or “create” the truthmakers that make our propositions true:
“They are just there or not there, whatever our opinion about them is.”
(Armstrong 2004, p. 33.) Just so – at the empirical level, as we might say. But
at the more metaphysically relevant level of the very categorizing of reality
(at a transcendental level, as we may
call it, if we are not afraid of Kantian notions), things are not so simple.
Can we simply claim that, e.g., universals instantiated in particulars (such
instantiations thereby forming states of affairs) in the world in itself make
our predicative statements (or, rather, the propositions those statements
express) true? For a pragmatically inclined thinker, such a claim would be a
monstrous example of a commitment to an underlying, ready-made structure of
reality as such, a structure in virtue of which, mysteriously, our statements (or the propositions they
express) would be true (or false). Inasmuch as pragmatists have found the
traditional correspondence relation mysterious or unhelpful, the same charge
should be directed against the truthmaking relation – if construed in a
metaphysically realist fashion in Armstrong’s manner. In order to be able to
make any proposition true, the world, as suggested above, must first be “made”
(and “remade”) by us, turned into a meaningfully categorized shape. Only as
thus categorized can it make any proposition true. The notion of making has no
meaning here unless it is a relation obtaining between identifiable items; any
identification, in turn, requires human conceptual categorization.[5]
Moreover, Armstrong’s metaphysically realist theory of truthmaking can
be subjected to a self-reflective critical analysis. Suppose his theory (and
the metaphysical realism that functions as its base) is true. What is the
truthmaker for this truth (in the
theory’s own terms)? Perhaps the truthmaker is whatever makes true the modal
truth that, necessarily, a truthmaking relation obtains between any truth and
the piece of world in virtue of which it is true. Then a truthmaker for this
modal truth could be provided in the way Armstrong (2004, ch. 8) proposes. But
why should the truthmaking theory be necessarily true? Could we have any
legitimate reasons for claiming that it lies in the necessary, unchanging
structure of things that truths are made true by truthmakers? This kind of a
position would hardly be preferable to a Platonic metaphysics of immutable
forms. Rather, as a pervasive feature of the fully contingent natural world (to
which even propositions belong, on Armstrong’s deflationary construal), the
truthmaking theory should, one might claim, be a contingent truth, or a true
generalization, perhaps comparable to laws of nature. Yet, this is hardly
plausible, either. The truthmaking theory is a piece of analytic ontology, not
a scientific theory. It is hard to see how it could be scientifically evaluated
or tested; it has no clear empirical content. On the other hand, it is no mere
convention; according to Armstrong, it is supposed to make a great difference
what kind of metaphysical views a person holds.
Thus, we observe that the status of Armstrong’s own views is unclear and
problematic. It is not at all obvious how his metaphysical findings, including
the truthmaking theory itself, are related to our advanced (and fallible)
scientific theories (whose truths, he supposes, we should also provide truthmakers
for). The same troubles haunt all those philosophers who, like Armstrong, seek
to combine metaphysical theorizing about ultimate reality with a naturalistic
respect for the advancement of science. On the most general level, the critic
may ask what (according to metaphysical realists) makes metaphysical realism
itself true. Is it the world itself, or whatever is the case? This answer can
hardly be non-question-beggingly defended against the critic of metaphysical
realism. Could future science show, for instance, that the theory of
truthmaking is false, or that metaphysical realism is false, or that a
factualist ontology of states of affairs is false? Are these questions even
meaningful, according to an ontologist like Armstrong – and if not, what is the
criteria of distinguishing meaningful questions from meaningless ones here (see
also Pihlström 2006b)?
In my view, it is much more plausible and straightforward, as well as
pragmatically better justifiable, to interpret the truthmaking theory as a human-made truth (if, indeed, we can
speak about its truth at all), as a pragmatically efficacious way of analyzing
the relation between the elements of the (empirical, cognizable) world and the
things we (can) say about that world. This theory is, then, something that our activities, in particular our
ontological theorizings, by means of which we categorize the world (always
ultimately guided by pragmatic considerations), make true. Without such a
pragmatic background, the truthmaking theory (or any general ontological view)
is hardly even a candidate for truth or falsity. For the pragmatist, moreover,
there is no problem with a vicious regress here: the pragmatic theory of truth,
as James (1909a, ch. 8) pointed out, is itself (hopefully) a pragmatically satisfactory
account of the concepts of truth and reality. The same can be expected to hold
about any pragmatic “theory” of any philosophically significant concept,
including the concept of truthmaking, insofar as such a theory can be
legitimately called “pragmatic”. This is a further consideration in favor of
pragmatism, to be added to the unclarity and sheer implausibility of the
metaphysical realist’s postulation of mysterious cross-categorial necessitating
relations (etc.) in order to explain our perfectly ordinary concepts of truth
and the world. Unlike metaphysical realism, pragmatism is a philosophical
interpretation of the concepts of truth and reality that can be readily applied
to itself, so as to account for its own truth.
It is, then, the pragmatic efficacy of our beliefs about the world that
makes (in a broadly interpreted sense) those beliefs true, by making us able to
orientate in the world they are about. This is (pragmatically!) true about our
“first-order” beliefs as well as about our “higher-level”, meta-level beliefs
about what it means to say that pragmatism is a true account of truth(making).
We might consider this proposal a partial vindication of James’s pragmatist
conception of truth and reality, without any commitment to his specific (often
misunderstood) doctrine of the utility or satisfactoriness of true beliefs.
5.
Conclusion
I have suggested above that we can retain our ordinary ontological
commitments to whatever truthmakers we pragmatically need for our truths –
e.g., states of affairs, properties (whether construed as universals, as
tropes, or as something different), and possibly even modalities – within a
pragmatist ontological framework which carefully avoids the dubious claim that
the world as it is in itself, entirely independently of us, is ontologically
prestructured so that it could (even in principle) be described from a
God’s-Eye-View when described in terms of these (or any other) truthmakers. The
notion of truthmaking, as well as the ontological method of providing truthmakers
for propositions we take to be true, may itself be a rather extraordinary
innovation, remote from our everyday practices, but the ontological commitments
our use of this notion (and method) yields may be perfectly ordinary,
pragmatically valuable ones. In this manner, even a qualified agreement with an
ontological scheme such as Armstrong’s is possible for the pragmatist who
insists on the pragmatic core of each and every ontological commitment.
Arguably, pragmatism is even better equipped for truthmaking theorizing
than metaphysical realism is, because of pragmatism’s dynamic view of truth as
a process within human experience.
The metaphilosophical moral to be drawn from all this is that the sharp
dichotomies between metaphysics (or ontology) and epistemology one finds in
authors like Armstrong – and in many other places as well, e.g., in a number of
contributions to Alston (2002) – are unacceptable. Truths are made precisely
because we make them in and through
our experience, which is itself in and of the natural world we live in. This is
a circular picture, of course, but hardly viciously so; more generally
speaking, pragmatism cannot avoid circularity, insofar as its own commitments
are to be pragmatically evaluated.
As is well known, pragmatism has been put forward as a serious
alternative to a number of traditional philosophical positions and
methodologies in several different fields of philosophy, e.g., in epistemology,
the philosophy of science, ethics, political philosophy, and elsewhere. The success
of pragmatism in these various fields seems to be based on its versatility.
Philosophers of widely different persuasions, favoring wildly different
substantial views, can hold on to pragmatist principles, often modifying them
for their own purposes. James (1907, ch. 2) compared pragmatism to a corridor
leading to an indefinite number of rooms in which one can find very different
intellectual work being done. It remains to be seen whether pragmatism can make
its way into the core areas of contemporary (analytic) metaphysics, such as the
theory of truthmaking, which may seem to be unpragmatist by definition but
which need not be – if the arguments put forward in this paper are on the right
track. No detailed pragmatist theory of truthmaking has (yet) been formulated
here, but perhaps the groundwork for such a theory has been done by making it
clear that the pragmatist need not be afraid of using that concept.
Acknowledgments
I am grateful to my
metaphysically (and realistically!) inclined colleagues (in particular, Prof.
Ilkka Niiniluoto and Dr. Heikki J. Koskinen) for several discussions
surrounding the topics of this paper, and to Prof. Charbel Niño El-Hani for
first suggesting to me that an investigation of a pragmatist theory of
truthmaking might be worthwhile.
REFERENCES
Alston,
William P. 1996. A Realist Conception of
Truth.
Alston,
William P. (ed.) 2002. Realism and
Antirealism.
Armstrong,
D.M. 1997. A World of States of Affairs.
Armstrong,
D.M. 2004. Truth and Truthmakers.
Chrudzimski,
Arkadiusz. 2002. “Objects, Properties and States of Affairs: An Aristotelian
Ontology of Truthmaking”, Axiomathes
13, 187-215.
Cox,
Damian. 1997. “The Trouble with Truth-Makers”, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 78, 45-62.
Davidson,
Donald. 1984. Inquiries into Truth and
Interpretation.
Davidson,
Donald. 1990. “The Structure and Content of Truth”, The Journal of Philosophy 87, 279-328.
Goodman,
Nelson. 1978. Ways of Worldmaking.
Hassocks: Harvester Press, 1992.
Goodman,
Nelson. 1984. Of Mind and Other Matters.
James,
William. 1907/1909a. Pragmatism: A New
Name for Some
James,
William. 1909b. A Pluralistic Universe.
Eds. Frederick H. Burkhardt, Fredson Bowers & Ignas K. Skrupskelis.
Kant,
Immanuel. 1781/1787. Kritik der reinen
Vernunft. Ed. Raymund Schmidt. Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 1990.
Kirkham,
Richard L. 1992. Theories of Truth: A
Critical Introduction.
Lewis,
David. 1986. On the Plurality of Worlds.
McCormick,
Peter J. (ed.) 1996. Starmaking: Realism,
Anti-Realism, and Irrealism.
Mulligan,
Kevin, Simons, Peter & Smith, Barry. 1984. “Truth-Makers”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research
44, 287-321.
Niiniluoto,
Ilkka. 1999. Critical Scientific Realism.
Niiniluoto,
Ilkka. 2004. “Tarski’s Definition and Truth-Makers”, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 126, 57-76.
Parsons,
Josh. 1999. “There is No ‘Truthmaker’ Argument against Nominalism”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 77,
325-334.
Pihlström,
Sami. 1996. Structuring the World: The
Issue of Realism and the Nature of Ontological Problems in Classical and
Contemporary Pragmatism. Acta Philosophica Fennica 59.
Pihlström,
Sami. 1998. Pragmatism and Philosophical Anthropology:
Understanding Our Human Life in a Human World.
Pihlström,
Sami. 2003. Naturalizing the
Transcendental: A Pragmatic View.
Pihlström,
Sami. 2004a. “Putnam and Rorty on Their Pragmatist Heritage: Re-reading James
and Dewey.” In Elias L. Khalil (ed.), Dewey,
Pragmatism, and Economic Methodology.
Pihlström,
Sami. 2004b. “Peirce’s Place in the Pragmatist Tradition.” In Cheryl Misak
(ed.), The
Pihlström,
Sami. 2005. Pragmatic Moral Realism: A
Transcendental Defense.
Pihlström,
Sami. 2006a. “Putnam’s Conception of Ontology”, forthcoming in Contemporary Pragmatism 3 (Book
Symposium on Putnam 2004).
Pihlström,
Sami. 2006b. “Armstrong’s Metaphysical Realism”, forthcoming in Markku Keinänen
& Tim de Mey (eds.), Problems from
Armstrong. Acta Philosophica Fennica.
Putnam,
Hilary. 1981. Reason, Truth and History.
Putnam,
Hilary. 1990. Realism with a Human Face.
Ed. James Conant.
Putnam,
Hilary. 1992. Renewing Philosophy.
Putnam,
Hilary. 1994. Words and Life. Ed.
James Conant.
Putnam,
Hilary. 1995. Pragmatism: An Open
Question.
Putnam,
Hilary. 1999. The Threefold Cord: Mind,
Body, and World.
Putnam,
Hilary. 2004. Ethics without Ontology.
Schiller,
F.C.S. 1907. Studies in Humanism.
Seibt, Johanna. 2000.
“Ontological Categories: The Explanation of Categorial Inference.” In D.
Greimann & C. Peres (eds.), System,
Struktur, Wahrheit. Olms Verlag, pp. 272-297.
Shook,
John R. (ed.) 2003. Pragmatic Naturalism
and Realism.
Smith,
Barry. 1999. “Truthmaker Realism”, Australasian
Journal of Philosophy 77, 274-291.
Wittgenstein,
Ludwig. 1921. Tractatus
logico-philosophicus: Logisch-philosophische Abhandlung. Frankfurt am Main:
Suhrkamp, 1964.
van
Woudenberg, René. 2002. “On the Metaphysical Implications of Alethic Realism.”
In Alston 2002, pp. 119-130.
NOTES
[1] This section will summarize some main points in Armstrong (2004). For a
more metaphilosophically oriented discussion of Armstrong, raising the problem
of the relation between his scientific naturalism and apparently
first-philosophical metaphysics, see Pihlström (2006b). Armstrong's detailed
arguments for his views on the truthmakers of, e.g., modal truths will not be
discussed here. See also his earlier (Armstrong 1997, ch. 8) “truthmaker
argument” for the postulation of states of affairs. While I will have something
to say about states of affairs later, Armstrong's “factualist” ontology (which
is partly indebted to Russell and to Wittgenstein's Tractatus) cannot be
examined in any detail here. The key idea, very simply, is that states of
affairs are needed as the truthmakers of truths of the form a is F. Along these
lines, it turns out, according to Armstrong, to be necessary to postulate both
particulars and universals as constituents of states of affairs.
[2] For rival views, which do not find the maximalist principle inevitable,
see, e.g., Smith (1999), Chrudzimski (2002) and, again, Lillehammer &
Rodriguez-Pereyra (2003), especially D.H. Mellor’s contribution. Parsons (1999)
distinguishes the (maximalist) “truthmaker principle” (every truth has a
truthmaker, in virtue of which that truth is true) from what he calls
“truthmaker essentialism” (the thesis that “every truth has a truthmaker, which is essentially that truth’s truthmaker”),
arguing (contra Armstrong) that one
can hold both the truthmaker principle and nominalism.
[3] On the correspondence theory (explicated along Tarskian lines), see
further Niiniluoto (1999) and (2004). In the latter paper, Niiniluoto argues
that the Tarskian semantic conception of truth can accommodate the realist idea
of truthmaking. Citing Mulligan et al.
(1984), he expresses sympathy with the view of tropes as truthmakers, though he
goes on to consider facts as truthmakers (Niiniluoto 2004, p. 67). On “alethic
realism”, or a realist conception of truth, see also Alston (1996) and several
papers collected in Alston (2002).
[4] The need to account for totality states of affairs in truthmaking
theory has been emphasized by Cox (1997). Armstrong’s (2004, pp. 78-79)
discussion is meant to face the problems raised by Cox: while there may be an
infinite regress of truths about totality, no increase in being is required
(see also Armstrong 1997, pp. 198-199). Niiniluoto (2004, p. 68) believes the
problem of totality is merely epistemic; Armstrong would surely disagree.
[5] This idea summarizes some of the views more thoroughly examined in my
as yet unpublished paper, “Transcendental Philosophy as an Ontology”, which defends
the idea of metaphysics as investigating (in a Kantian or quasi-Kantian manner)
a humanly categorized reality, as distinguished from a reality absolutely
independent of us. I should note, however, that there are “truthmaker realists”
(who would hardly wish to commit themselves to anything like “transcendental
philosophy”) such as Barry Smith (1999, pp. 289-290), who argues that
truthmakers should be regarded as “cognition-dependent entities” existing “as a
result of certain sorts of cognitively effected demarcations of reality”, that
is, as “gerrymandered” “human constructions” in the sense that they “come to be
delineated in reality only in virtue of corresponding cognitive practices on
the part of human beings”, while being (despite their practice- or
cognition-dependence) genuinely “chunks of reality”. Smith’s position differs
both from Armstrong’s and from the pragmatists’.
Copyright © 2005 Minerva
All rights are reserved, but
fair and good faith use with full attribution may be made of this work for
educational or scholarly purposes.
Sami Pihlström is Professor of Philosophy at the University of
Tampere, Finland, and Docent of Theoretical Philosophy at the University of
Helsinki,
Return
to Minerva (Volume 9) Main Page
Go to Top of This Page