ISSN 1393-614X Minerva - An Internet Journal of
Philosophy Vol. 9 2005.
____________________________________________________
Nietzsche on the Possibility of Truth and Knowledge Tsarina Doyle |
This paper examines Nietzsche’s views on
truth and knowledge in the context of both his rejection of the Kantian thing-in-itself
and his perspectivism. It is argued that Nietzsche’s principal contention with
the thing-in-itself centres round the dissociation of truth and justification.
The paper argues that Nietzsche’s perspectivism, understood as an epistemic
thesis, sows the seeds for the overcoming of this sceptical dissociation.
Nietzsche’s thoughts on the issues of truth and
knowledge permeate his entire philosophical corpus and have proven to be the
most disputed in the Nietzsche canon. This is arguably because Nietzsche often
refers to these issues in some wider context, as they direct his views on
other, less obviously epistemological, issues. One often finds, for example,
that Nietzsche refers to or even presupposes various epistemological commitments
in his discussions of value. Thus it is arguably the case that Nietzsche’s
primary philosophical concerns are not epistemological in character. However,
it seems to me that particular epistemological commitments inform much of what
Nietzsche has to say on other issues. This is suggested, for example, when he
writes of the “self-overcoming of morality through truthfulness” (Nietzsche,
1992, “Why I am a Destiny”, 3) and when he states that “the importance of
knowledge for life ought to appear as
great as possible” (Nietzsche, 1994, 6). Any interpretation of Nietzsche’s
ideas on the issues of truth and knowledge requires, then, a degree of
excavation. Karl Japers’ comparison of Nietzsche’s writings to a destroyed
building that must be reconstructed from the hints and clues provided by its
ruins is particularly apt here (Jaspers,
1993, pp.3-4). For it draws our attention to both the role of the interpreter
of Nietzsche’s writings and the need to reconstruct Nietzsche’s arguments.[1] It is on the basis of this type of understanding of
Nietzsche’s project and one’s interpretive engagement with it that I shall
propose that a non-sceptical position informs Nietzsche’s writings.[2] However, any attempt to do this is compounded by
Nietzsche’s use of the language of falsification to describe the status of our
beliefs. This difficulty is not helped by the fact that sometimes Nietzsche
combines statements regarding the erroneous nature of our beliefs with more
straightforward truth claims. For example, in Beyond Good and Evil, 229 he claims to reveal truths that have
remained hidden for centuries whilst declaring all our beliefs to be false.
This, however, would suggest that Nietzsche thought that his use of the
language of falsification is compatible with his more positive philosophical
claims. Moreover, in many of the passages where Nietzsche describes what
falsification entails, he does so in terms of simplification.[3] This further suggests that when Nietzsche articulates
the falsification thesis it is not global error that he has predominantly in
mind, but rather “narrow” perspectives as opposed to more “comprehensive”
perspectives. Throughout the paper, I shall suggest that Nietzsche’s
anti-sceptical argument emerges and takes shape in the context of both Nietzsche’s
rejection of the intelligibility of the thing-in-itself and his perspectivism
as a response to what he sees as the dissociation of truth and justification in
the history of philosophy.[4] I shall use the term “metaphysical realism”[5] to capture this dissociation because, for Nietzsche,
as we shall see, the dissociation of truth and justification has been
intertwined with a particular dualist form of metaphysics throughout its
history.
Nietzsche contends that
philosophy has hitherto operated within a dualistic appearance/reality
dichotomy where reality is deemed to be an extra-empirical
realm of truth whilst the actual empirical world of our ordinary experience is
deemed to be a realm of deception and untruth.[6] It is thus Nietzsche’s
contention that philosophy has operated within a metaphysical realist paradigm.
I employ the term metaphysical realism here to denote the view that reality has
a determinate nature, which is cognitively inaccessible to our natural means of
knowing about the world. Of particular interest to Nietzsche is its claim that
reality is epistemically divorced from human cognitive subjects. He writes:
[---]
stricter logicians, after they had rigorously established the concept of the
metaphysical as the concept of that which is unconditioned and consequently
unconditioning, denied any connection between the unconditioned (the
metaphysical world) and the world we are familiar with. So that the thing-in-itself does not appear in the world of
appearances, [my italics], and any conclusion about the former on the basis
of the latter must be rejected. (Nietzsche, 1994, 16)
As such, the metaphysical
realist implies that even our in principle best-justified beliefs may be radically
false. They may be false in the sense that they fail to mirror reality as it is
independently of our cognitive constitution. According to Nietzsche, this
metaphysical realist desire to mirror reality as it is in itself requires a
conception of the cognitive subject as one unhindered by particular cognitive
interests. Metaphysical realism thus adopts a God’s Eye View or
supra-perspectival standard of both truth and reality. Nietzsche’s disagreement
with the metaphysical realist involves, in a similar fashion to Michael
Williams, not “our trying to ‘understand objective knowledge’ but rather our
trying to ‘understand knowledge objectively,’ i.e. from the ‘detached,’
philosophical perspective.” (Williams, 1991, p. 254)[7] Thus Nietzsche’s
disagreement centres round the epistemological thesis contained in metaphysical
realism. This epistemological thesis maintains that our knowledge is only
adequate to reality if that knowledge is extra-perspectival and therefore
non-anthropocentric in character. This epistemic thesis is articulated in
metaphysical realism in two ways. For metaphysical realists can, in Nietzsche’s
view, be divided into two groups. We can characterize them as either
cognitivists or non-cognitivists with regard to the knowability of the metaphysical
“real” world. The cognitivist claims that reality is both accessible and
knowable through a special faculty that allows direct and unmediated knowledge
of ultimate reality. However, metaphysical realists of the non-cognitivist
persuasion argue that reality as it is in itself is inaccessible. Rationalist
metaphysicians represent the former. The latter view arrives on the
philosophical scene, according to Nietzsche, in the guise of Kant. This
non-cognitivist form of metaphysical realism emerges following the demise of
the cognitivist version. Thus in order to better understand Nietzsche’s
critique I shall adumbrate both versions in turn.
Nietzsche argues that the
aforementioned metaphysical realist practice of devaluing the empirical world
has its roots in the rationalist appeal to a
priori Reason as the source of knowledge of the “real” world. By this I
mean that it is Nietzsche’s view that rationalist metaphysics claim to have
unmediated conceptual access to an extra-empirical realm of reality as it is in
itself. Its concepts are presented as something innate and certain as opposed
to Nietzsche’s view that they have evolved over a period of time:
Hitherto one
has generally trusted one’s concepts as if they were a wonderful dowry from
some sort of wonderland: but they are, after all, the inheritance from our most
remote, most foolish as well as most intelligent ancestors. (Nietzsche, 1968,
409)
Thus, of the cognitivist metaphysical realist model,
Nietzsche claims that “Reality is nowhere to be found in them, not even as a
problem.” (Nietzsche, 1998c, III.3) He argues that this particular
interpretation of the world is “fabricated solely from psychological needs”
(Nietzsche, 1968, 12A) and that once this has been revealed through
genealogical and historical inquiry, the dissolution of this metaphysical
picture will be inevitable. (Nietzsche,
1994, 1) Genealogy inquires into the contingent origins of a belief whilst
historical inquiry traces the development of the belief. Nietzsche claims that
once the psychological and moral ulterior guiding motives behind the invention
of the metaphysical dualism are revealed, this dualism will be refuted:
Metaphysical world. It
is true, there might be a metaphysical world; one can hardly dispute the
absolute possibility of it. We see all things by means of our human head, and
cannot chop it off, though it remains to wonder what would be left of the world
if indeed it had been cut off. This is a purely scientific problem, and not
very suited to cause men worry. But all that has produced metaphysical
assumptions and made them valuable,
horrible, pleasurable to men thus far is passion, error, and
self-deception. The very worst methods of knowledge, not the very best, have
taught us to believe in them. When one
has disclosed these methods to be the foundation of all existing religions and
metaphysical systems, one has refuted them. [my italics] (Nietzsche, 1994,
9)
Metaphysical realism, in its cognitivist guise, becomes an untenable
philosophical position, according to Nietzsche, once the will to truth undermines itself. It does this in the sense that it
can no longer endorse the belief in the “true” world once genealogical and
historical inquiry reveal its origins. Nietzsche writes:
But
among the forces cultivated by morality was truthfulness:
this eventually turned against morality, discovered its teleology, its
partial perspective - and now the recognition of this inveterate mendaciousness
that one despairs of shedding becomes a stimulant. Now we discover in ourselves
needs implanted by centuries of moral interpretation - needs that now appear to
us as needs for untruth; on the other hand, the value for which we endure life
seems to hinge on these needs. This antagonism - not to esteem what we know, and not to be allowed any longer to esteem the lies we should like to tell
ourselves - results in a process of dissolution. (Nietzsche, 1968, 5)
Peter Poellner (2001)
appeals to Human, All Too Human, to
support what he calls Nietzsche’s metaphysical indifferentist argument against
the thing-in-itself. This argument entails, according to Poellner, that it is
possible that there is a metaphysical world, but that this theoretical
possibility bears no practical consequences for us. However, Nietzsche’s
reference to the metaphysical world in Human, All Too Human, 9, it seems
to me, is highly ambiguous. On one level it appears to refer to a theoretical
possibility that bears no practical implications. On a second level, however,
Nietzsche adopts a stronger position that rejects, in his view, the possibility
of a metaphysical world. He contends that this possibility has been “refuted”
by showing that the methodology informing it is unreliable. Moreover, he
contends in Human, All Too Human, 16 that the metaphysical world is only
capable of a negative definition that is lacking in meaning. The addition of
this second level renders Nietzsche’s argument here stronger than the
indifferentist interpretation. The stronger argument implies that there cannot
be a thing-in-itself whose nature is radically different from the world that we
are familiar with and thus capable of casting our beliefs into radical doubt.
Either way, however, Nietzsche suggests that the very idea of the
thing-in-itself is epistemically impotent.
The collapse of the cognitivist
version of metaphysical realism indicates, in Nietzsche’s view, the
untenability of the extra-perspectival conception of knowing inherent in the
God’s Eye View of knowledge. Although this is an important aspect of his
complete rejection of metaphysical realism, Nietzsche argues that the
revelation that Reason is not an objective and disinterested cognitive tool
that facilitates access to the world as it is in itself does not result in the
complete collapse of metaphysical realism. Rather, metaphysical realism merely
adopts a non-cognitivist stance with regard to the “real” world. In his outline
of the history of philosophy in Twilight
of the Idols, Nietzsche traces the progressive demise of the rationalist
conception of reality and our knowledge of it. I will cite this passage for the
convenience of the reader.
HOW THE ‘REAL WORLD’ FINALLY BECAME A FABLE
History of an Error
1. The real world attainable for the wise man, the
pious man, the virtuous man – he lives in it, he is it.
(Most ancient form of the idea, relatively clever,
simple, convincing. Paraphrase of the proposition: ‘I, Plato, am the truth’).
2. The real world unattainable for now, but promised to
the wise man, the pious man, the virtuous man (‘to the sinner who repents’).
(Progress of the idea: it becomes more cunning, more
insidious, more incomprehensible – it
becomes a woman, it becomes Christian---)
3. The real world unattainable, unprovable,
unpromisable, but the mere thought of it a consolation, an obligation, an
imperative.
(The old sun in the background, but seen through
mist and scepticism; the idea become sublime, pale, Nordic, Königsbergian.)
4. The real world – unattainable? At any rate
unattained. And since unattained also unknown.
Hence no consolation, redemption, obligation either: what could something
unknown oblige us to do?---
(Break of day. First yawn of reason. Cock-crow of
positivism.)
5. The ‘real world’ – an idea with no further use, no
longer even an obligation – an idea become useless, superfluous, therefore a refuted idea: let us do away
with it!
(Broad daylight; breakfast; return of bons sens and cheerfulness; Plato’s
shameful blush; din from all free spirits.)
6. The real world – we have done away with it: what
world was left? the apparent one, perhaps?---But no! with the real world we have also done away with the apparent one!
(Noon; moment of the shortest shadow; end of the
longest error; pinnacle of humanity; INCIPIT ZARATHUSTRA.) (Nietzsche, 1998c,
IV)
Nietzsche’s complaint here
centres round his belief that philosophy has operated within a dualistic, two-world model.
According to this model, our knowledge can only be adequate to reality if we
disengage ourselves from our particular anthropocentric interests. Stages one
to four in Nietzsche’s history of philosophy represent this two-world mode of
thinking that has its origins in Platonism and Christianity. It is significant
for our purposes that Nietzsche places Kant at stage three, thus indicating
that he considers that Kant too operates within this two-world mode of thinking.
According to Nietzsche, Kant retains the rationalist faith in metaphysical
realism in the guise of the inaccessible and unknowable thing-in-itself. In so
doing, Kant adopts, in Nietzsche’s view, the non-cognitivist strain of
metaphysical realism. Nietzsche argues that Kant belongs to this metaphysical
realist category because he retains the thing-in-itself as a metaphysical
hangover from rationalist metaphysics.[8] This hangover results, in
Nietzsche’s view, from Kant’s acceptance of the demise of unmediated conceptual
knowledge coupled with his retention of the idea that our human cognitive
machinery is unable to provide insight into the ultimate nature of reality.
In the final stage of his
outline of the history of the “true” world Nietzsche indicates, by naming his
mythic mouthpiece Zarathustra, that his own philosophy will take upon itself
the task of undermining this two-world approach. Since Nietzsche thinks that
the cognitivist version has suffered a death by its own hands it remains for
him to overcome the non-cognitivist version of metaphysical realism. I shall
begin to examine the manner in which Nietzsche succeeds in doing this in the
next two sections. It will be seen that Nietzsche’s main contention with
metaphysical realism centers round the issue of the justification of our epistemic claims. Truth and justification
comprise, for the metaphysical realist, a correspondence between the way the
world is in itself and our epistemic and normative assertions. With the demise
of the cognitivist version, however, and its metamorphosis into the
non-cognitivist version, we witness what may be termed a decoupling[9] of truth and
justification, whereby our ordinary experience of the world and the
justification of our epistemic claims are denied the title “truth”. Thus
according to this version, truth-in-itself and our actual practices of
justification are radically divorced. In such a case we witness what Nietzsche
terms a severing of theory from practice. In theory, the non-cognitivist
metaphysical realist adopts a foundationalist approach to the question of truth
and justification. However, in practice, given the cognitive inaccessibility of
truth-in-itself, the non-cognitive metaphysical realist operates with possible
falsehoods and illusions. Nietzsche’s anti-metaphysical realism aims to
overcome this underlying foundationalist approach. If he is to succeed in this
he must overcome the non-cognitivist version of metaphysical realism by
recoupling truth and justification. He does this, as we shall see, by both
demonstrating the incoherence of the idea of the thing-in-itself and by
adopting a contextualist, anti-foundationalist conception of justification.
Contrary to the non-cognitivist metaphysical realist idea of inaccessible
“truth-in-itself” and the consequent dissociation of truth and justification
that this entails, Nietzsche claims that our practices of justification
determine truth. With this in mind I shall proceed by turning to Nietzsche’s perspectivism.
Nietzsche and Perspectivism
Understood as a form of anti-foundationalist thought, Nietzsche’s perspectivism is designed to counteract
the metaphysical realist correspondence theory of truth and justification. In
so doing, Nietzsche aims to replace the metaphysical realist view from nowhere with the perspectivist view
from somewhere. He defines a
perspective as an “interest of certain types of life” (Nietzsche, 1968, 293)
arguing that our truths are irretrievably entwined with our interests. Perspectivism aims to induce, contrary
to the metaphysical realist, a form of epistemological modesty by claiming that
we cannot acquire extra-perspectival knowledge. Extra-perspectival knowledge is conceivable, according to
Nietzsche, only if we permit both the objectionable concept of the thing-in-itself
or Platonic eternal verities and the necessary rationalist cognitive tools.
However, Nietzsche contends that his genealogical argument has shown that what
has been considered to be extra-perspectival knowledge has actually been only a
perspective.[10] He further supplements this empirical
argument with an a priori one that
suggests that the very idea of a view from nowhere is contradictory.
For let us guard ourselves better from
now on, gentlemen philosophers, against the dangerous old conceptual
fabrication that posited a “pure, will-less, painless, timeless subject of
knowledge”; let us guard ourselves against the tentacles of such contradictory
concepts as “pure reason,” “absolute spirituality,” “knowledge in itself”: here
it is always demanded that we think an eye that cannot possibly be thought, an
eye that must not have any direction, in which the active and interpretive
forces through which seeing first becomes seeing-something are to be shut off,
are to be absent; thus, what is demanded here is always an absurdity and
non-concept of an eye. (Nietzsche, 1998b, III:12)
Since the God’s Eye View and the thing-in-itself are mutually dependent
on one another, according to Nietzsche, the demise of one must lead to the
inevitable collapse of the other. For Nietzsche argues that the distinction
between appearances and things-in-themselves is only made intelligible by the
conceivability of a God’s Eye View. The inconceivability of such a view,
Nietzsche contends, removes the basis of scepticism founded on this
distinction. He thus claims that the concept of the
thing-in-itself or a metaphysical world that is inaccessible to our cognitive
faculties is also a contradiction in terms. Nietzsche argues that it is
impossible to conceptualize such a notion. He writes:
But I shall repeat a hundred times over
that the ‘immediate certainty’, like ‘absolute knowledge’ and the ‘thing in
itself’, contains a contradictio in
adjecto: it’s time people freed themselves from the seduction of words!
(Nietzsche, 1998a, 16)
Nietzsche contends that the thing-in-itself is an idea “empty of
meaning” (Nietzsche, 1994, 16) that can only be defined negatively. (Ibid.) Any attempt to conceptualize what is perforce for
Nietzsche unconceptualizable is a fruitless activity to the extent that, he
argues, “We cannot look around our own corner: it is a hopeless curiosity that
wants to know what other kinds of intellects and perspectives there might be [---].” (Nietzsche, 1974, 374)
`
With his argument regarding the unintelligibility of both the God’s Eye
View and the thing-in-itself, Nietzsche introduces the criteria for his
anti-metaphysical realism. The reach of our perspectives becomes the boundary
of both intelligibility and rational acceptability. Thus perspectivism narrows the issue of truth to truth “for us” as
opposed to, what he considers to be, the implausible metaphysical realist
notion of truth-in-itself. In so doing, Nietzsche denies contrary to the
metaphysical realist, that reality is epistemically inaccessible to our cognitive
constitution.
Maudemarie Clark captures Nietzsche’s
thinking in this respect when she defines metaphysical realism as the view that
truth is independent of both our cognitive capacities and cognitive interests.
(Clark, 1990, p.48) Our cognitive capacities are
subject to development and change. It is thus conceivable that there are
cognitive subjects with greater cognitive abilities than us to the extent that
they have enhanced observational capacities. Our cognitive interests, on the
other hand, may be construed as that which “we could ever want” (Clark, 1990,
p. 98) from a theory.
Truth is independent not simply of what
we now want, but of what we could ever want, that is, of what we would want
even under ideal conditions for inquiry for beings like ourselves. (Clark,
1990, p. 48)
This view leaves open the possibility that our beliefs may be massively
in error in a similar manner to Descartes’ subject deceived by the demon or the
brain in a vat that is deceived by the master scientist. Given this
possibility, the metaphysical realist thinks it intelligible that our beliefs
about the world may be illusory, bearing no significant cognitive relation to
how the world is in itself. Such a view considers truth to be independent of
both our cognitive capacities and interests. The situation depicted in the
demon scenario transcends our capacities in the sense that it is beyond our
sensory detective abilities alone to discern whether the beliefs induced in us
by the demon are adequate to the true nature of reality. It is independent of
our interests to the extent that it implies that, without a divine guarantee, a
theory that gave us all we could ever want from a theory might nevertheless be
massively in error.
Thus truth is independent of our cognitive interests if it is claimed
that our cognitive engagement with the world may be radically false. In order
to close the possibility of massive error, anti-metaphysical realism, in
contrast, must maintain that truth is dependent on our cognitive interests but
independent of our cognitive capacities. It must be independent of our
cognitive capacities in order to allow for the real possibility of increased
observational abilities and discovery etc. However, it must be dependent upon
our cognitive interests in order to rule out the possibility of casting our
beliefs into massive error. Thus anti-metaphysical realist truth is dependent
on what we could ever want from a theory understood as that which is
intelligible to cognitive subjects with our mode of rationality. This entails
that a proposition or theory, which is supported by the best reasons we in
principle could have for holding that particular view, cannot be radically in
error. This is suggested by Nietzsche’s association of our best reasons (our
consideration of multiple perspectives and the balancing of reasons for and
against a view) with the quest for certainty:
[---] the great majority of people does not consider it contemptible to
believe this or that and to live accordingly, without first having given
themselves an account of the final and
most certain reasons pro and con [my italics], and without even troubling
themselves about such reasons afterward: [---] But what is goodheartedness,
refinement or genius to me, when the person who has these virtues tolerates
slack feelings in his faith and judgments and when he does not account the desire for certainty as his inmost
craving and deepest distress [----] (Nietzsche, 1974, 2)[12]
Here Nietzsche sets up the arena in which truth claims are to be
justified. If anti-metaphysical realist truth is independent of our cognitive
capacities but dependent on our cognitive interests, then, it is dependent on
what is intelligible or conceivable to us, and thus on our in principle best
reasons for holding a belief.[13] Thus
[---] truth is independent not only of
what we could in principle have
reason to accept, but also of what any
conceivable intelligence [my italics] could have reason to accept, given our best standards of rational
acceptability. (Clark, 1990, p.48)
The anti-metaphysical realist model outlined above is somewhat similar
to the one proffered by Donald Davidson. Davidson argues that it is conceivable
that there are beings with superior cognitive capacities to our own. Such a
being would be what Davidson terms the ‘omniscient interpreter’. According to
Davidson, the omniscient interpreter can only deem our beliefs false by
entering into cognitive communication with us. The possibility of such
communication, however, presupposes a background of agreement on most matters.
Thus, Davidson contends that “objective error can occur only in a setting of
largely true belief”. (Davidson, 1984, p. 200) From this we can see that the
omniscient interpreter can cast our perspectival belief into massive error only
within the framework of our own standards of rational acceptability. The
possibility of massive error, in other words, must be translatable into a
rational format familiar to us. Metaphysical realism, according to Nietzsche,
is one such untranslatable position. Such an untranslatable viewpoint can have,
in Nietzsche’s view, no cognitive purchase for us. It would be a view from
Nowhere, an impossible attempt to “look around our own corner”.
Two Objections
At this point it will be fruitful for us to consider two possible
objections to the reconstruction of Nietzsche’s anti-sceptical epistemology
outlined above. As I shall suggest, both objections emerge from a
misunderstanding of the role that Nietzsche’s perspectivism plays in this
epistemology. This specific role can be clarified by responding to these
objections.
The first objection argues that unless Nietzsche’s anti-metaphysical
realist account of truth allows for properties in the world that transcend our
interests or perspectives, Nietzsche is committed to a form of subjective idealism
in the sense that to be is to be of some interest to a human cognitive subject.[14] The second objection responds by
suggesting that if this is not the case and Nietzsche is not committed to such
an idealist view, then, he must allow for extra-perspectival properties in the
world and in so doing, Nietzsche despite his claims to the contrary, embraces
metaphysical realism.[15] In what follows I shall suggest that these
objections may be allowed to stand only if we construe Nietzsche’s
perspectivism as primarily a metaphysical thesis rather than an epistemic one.
In order to allay the
first objection, then, we must be clear about what is meant by perspectives or
cognitive interests. It seems to me that Nietzsche’s perspectivism must be construed primarily as an epistemic thesis
about the conditions of our knowledge. This is not to deny, however, that
Nietzsche puts forward a first-order perspectival thesis. The metaphysics of
the will to power puts forward the view that reality comprises a hierarchy of
perspectival forces. However, Nietzsche suggests that this metaphysical
position derives from his epistemic thesis regarding the importance of method
in the justification of our beliefs. He claims that “In the end, we are not
only allowed to perform such an experiment, we are commanded to do so by the
conscience of our method.”
(Nietzsche, 1998a, 36) Elsewhere he emphasizes the importance of methodology
when he writes “the most valuable insights are arrived at last; but the most
valuable insights are methods”. (Nietzsche,
1968, 469. Cf. Nietzsche, 1990, 59). As is evident from The Gay Science, 2 and On the
Genealogy of Morality, III, 12 rigorous methodology, for Nietzsche,
involves considering reasons for and against a belief. It involves a
multi-perspectival viewpoint. This does not involve seeing something from many
different perspectives simultaneously, but rather the attempt to view many
perspectives under one unifying comprehensive explanatory perspective. Thus
Nietzsche emphasizes the idea of a “uniform science” in The Anti-Christ, 59 and in Beyond
Good and Evil, 36 he sees the will to power as unifying perspectives
available in both the human and the natural sciences. The will to power
metaphysics is thus seen as a rejection of the mechanistic account of causality
and in BGE, 19 it accounts, in
Nietzsche’s view, for the complex phenomenon of human willing. On this basis,
it seems to me that Nietzsche’s perspectivism is primarily a second-order
thesis regarding the possibility of knowledge and the justification of our
beliefs. However, perspectivism is secondarily and in a derivative way, a
first-order metaphysical thesis about the constitution of reality and our
participation in it. The point that I want to make here is that within the
epistemic context in which we are presently discussing Nietzsche’s
perspectivism, I take perspectivism
to maintain that our manner of knowing the world is perspectival and not that
the world itself is metaphysically reducible
to our perspectives. Thus, for Nietzsche, perspectives at the second-order
level are conditions of knowing the
world but they do not constitute the world.[16] This does not, however,
reintroduce the very dualism that I have argued Nietzsche rejects. For Nietzsche’s
quarrel with the dualism inherent in metaphysical realism, we recall, centres
round the idea that ultimate reality is cognitively inaccessible by
perspectival means. We have seen that by rejecting the coherency of the
thing-in-itself Nietzsche contends that reality is in principle available to
our knowledge. However, he is concerned to emphasize the non-constitutive
nature of our knowing in order to avoid the idea that reality can be carved up
in multiple incommensurate ways. This idea would disallow the possibility that
some perspectives are more justified than others and would, consequently,
collapse into the very dissociation of truth and justification that he aims to
overcome. Nietzsche’s response to this dissociation, then, involves heeding Kant’s
warning that all knowledge takes place from the specifically human point of
view, whilst modifying Kant’s argument by claiming that our perspectives do not
“make” the world but rather regulatively “direct” our inquiry according to our
perspectival interests. By abandoning the idea that we constitute the world
Nietzsche argues that we are, as knowers, immersed within the world as evolving
parts of a larger whole. The world is thus no longer construed as an object
that is divorced from our knowledge but rather one that is available in
principle to our best practices of justification.
However, the second objection suggests that if our perspectives do not
constitute the world then Nietzsche must allow for extra-perspectival (that is,
non-reducible) properties in the world. The objection here is that if Nietzsche
does allow such non-reducible properties then he is guilty of metaphysical
realism. That he does allow that there are non-reducible properties in the
world can be seen from his many statements where he claims that we can only
selectively perceive the world. For example, he writes:
[---] we have senses for only a
selection of perceptions – those with which we have to concern ourselves in
order to preserve ourselves. (Nietzsche, 1968, 505)
In the light of the epistemic understanding of Nietzsche’s perspectivism that I am proposing, the
most fruitful way of reading Nietzsche’s rejection of metaphysical realism is
as a thesis about knowability. To re-iterate, metaphysical realism as it has
been presented in this paper represents, for Nietzsche, the view that the world
is inaccessible to our perspectival mode of knowing. Inaccessibility is here
taken as synonymous with the possibility of massive error. The world is
inaccessible in the light of the demise of pure a priori forms of knowledge, which it seems from my adumbration of
it earlier, is the only mode of access to the “real” world for the metaphysical
realist. The “true” world in this metaphysical realist sense, following the
demise of rationalist metaphysics, is construed as the “hidden” but proper foundation of our epistemological
claims. As such it is independent of our cognitive interests in the sense that
our human perspectival take on reality may be radically false. In this context
the possibility of non-reducible properties is problematic for Nietzsche only
if they are capable of casting our in principle best-justified perspectival
truths into massive error. However, we have seen that this possibility is
unintelligible in the sense of untranslatable to us and therefore of no
cognitive purchase. If this is the case, then, Nietzsche’s acceptance that the
world itself is metaphysically independent of us and so not reducible to our
perspectives is unproblematic for the status of our epistemic claims. What
Nietzsche’s perspectival theory of knowledge does rule out, however, is the
possibility of a supra-perspectival and therefore God’s Eye View of the world.
The God’s Eye View is committed to a recognition-transcendent view of truth. As
such Nietzsche’s metaphysical realist is akin to what John Haldane terms the
ultra-realist that insists upon “the unconditional transcendence of reality
over our natural means of coming to know about the world”. (Haldane, 1993, p.
34) We may construe Nietzsche’s perspectivism,
then, as an attempt to counteract such an ultra-realist foundationalist theory
in favour of a perspectival and anti-foundationalist view.
Thus Nietzsche construes perspectives as conditions of knowledge that
provide the contextual basis of justification. He writes:
There are no isolated judgments! An
isolated judgment is never ‘true’, never knowledge, only in the connection [Zusammenhange] and relation [Beziehung] of many judgments is there
any surety [Bürgschaft] (Nietzsche,
1968, 530)
Here Nietzsche suggests, contrary to the metaphysical realist, that the
standard of judgement is always another judgement. For Nietzsche, our beliefs
are not justified through extra-perspectival confrontation with the world. He
suggests that there are no privileged beliefs and that our beliefs must be
mutually reinforced in the context of other beliefs. From this we can see that
Nietzsche’s perspectivism rejects the
metaphysical realist understanding of objectivity as a God’s Eye View from
Nowhere in favour of a multi-perspectival viewpoint that overcomes the
metaphysical realist decoupling of truth and justification. This is achieved by
rejecting the notion of truth-in-itself in favour of Nietzsche’s conception of
truth for us whereby our in principle
best practices of justification determine truth.
There is only a perspectival seeing, only
a perspectival “knowing”; and the
more affects we allow to speak about a matter [---] that much more complete
will our “concept” of this matter, our “objectivity” be. (Nietzsche, 1998b,
III, 12)
It is suggested here that if objectivity is defined by our perspectival
take on the world, then truth cannot globally transcend our in principle
best-justified human beliefs. This does not mean that we have the best reasons
for supporting a belief right now. As such our predominant beliefs (our present
best-justified beliefs) may be erroneous or partial in some way. What it does
entail is that reality is not in principle cut off from our cognitive
constitution. Moreover, Nietzsche suggests that we have acquired sufficient
knowledge thus far to enable us to both proceed further with our investigations
and to adjudicate the epistemic worth of competing beliefs. This is suggested
by Nietzsche’s claim that although mechanism has understood the model of
causality incorrectly that does not mean that we abandon the concept of
causality or our search for causal laws in nature. Rather, for Nietzsche it
involves abandoning the mechanist ‘push and pull’ theory of causality in favour
of a more refined account of causal connection inspired by Boscovich’s physics
of action at a distance. Thus Nietzsche writes that we need not abandon the
concept of causality altogether. What we should reconsider, however, is what he
calls the “most usual explanations”. (Nietzsche, 1998c, VI: 5). Thus Nietzsche
suggests that much of what we accept as justified and true in the commonsense
world of our experience is a coarse understanding of things. Nietzsche argues
that a more finely grained or more comprehensive perspective is both possible
and desirable.
It is in this context that Nietzsche suggests that the recoupling of
truth and justification takes place by incorporating partial or limited
perspectives into the most comprehensive perspective on the nature of things.
The most comprehensive perspective, for Nietzsche, is one that sufficiently
explains the nature of the world and our participation in it. Thus he writes,
“every elevation of man brings with it the overcoming of narrower
interpretations”. (Nietzsche, 1968, 616). Nietzsche’s perspectivism thus
rejects the metaphysical realist quest for absolute standards of correctness.
An intrinsic component of this rejection is the dissolution of the distinction
between appearance and cognitively inaccessible reality. Rather, for Nietzsche,
what we have are more or less comprehensive perspectives on things or what he
calls lighter and darker shades of appearance. (Nietzsche, 1998a, 36). Within
these shades there is room for correction and revision. However, the idea of an
inaccessible reality and the related idea of massive error dissolves. Thus
Nietzsche can write that
The antithesis of the apparent world and
the true world is reduced to the antithesis “world” and “nothing”. (Nietzsche,
1968, 567)
Bibliography
Anderson, Lanier R. (1994)
“Nietzsche’s Will to Power as a Doctrine of the Unity of Science” in Studies
in History and Philosophy of Science, Volume 25.
________ (1996) “Overcoming
Charity: The Case of Maudemarie Clark’s Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy, in
Nietzsche-Studien, Band 25.
Clark, Maudemarie, (1990) Nietzsche
on Truth and Philosophy,
Cox, Christoph (1999) Nietzsche:
Naturalism and Interpretation,
Davidson, Donald (1984) “The
Method of Truth in Metaphysics” in Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation,
Green, Michael Steven (2002) Nietzsche
and the Transcendental Tradition,
Haldane, John (1993) “Mind-World
Identity Theory and the Anti-Realist Challenge” in John Haldane and Crispin
Wright eds., Reality, Representation and Projection, Oxford University
Press, Oxford.
Jaspers, Karl (1993) Nietzsche: An
Introduction to the Understanding of his Philosophical Activity, translated
by Charles F. Wallraff and Frederick J. Schmitz, The John Hopkins University
Press, London.
Leiter, Brian (1994) “Perspectivism in
Nietzsche’s Genealogy of Morals” in Richard Schacht, ed., Nietzsche,
Genealogy, Morality,
Nietzsche, Friedrich (1994) Human, All Too Human translated by
Marion Faber and Stephen Lehmann, Penguin,
_________ (1974) The Gay Science translated by Walter Kaufmann, Vintage Books,
_________
(1969) Thus
Spoke Zarathustra translated by R. J. Hollingdale, Penguin,
_________ (1998a) Beyond Good and Evil translated by Marion
Faber,
_________
(1998b) On
the Genealogy of Morality translated by Maudemarie Clark and Alan J. Swensen,
Hackett Publishing Company,
________ (1998c) Twilight of the Idols translated by Duncan Large,
_________
(1990) The
Anti-Christ translated by R. J. Hollingdale, Penguin,
_________
(1992) Ecce
Homo translated by R. J. Hollingdale, Penguin,
_________(1968) The Will to
Power translated by Walter Kaufmann, Vintage Books,
Owen, David (1995) Nietzsche,
Politics and Modernity, Sage Publications,
Poellner, Peter (1995) Nietzsche and
Metaphysics, Clarendon Press,
_______ (2001) “Perspectival Truth” in
John Richardson and Brian Leiter, eds. Nietzsche,
Ridley, Aaron (1998) Nietzsche’s
Conscience,
Rorty, Richard (1996) Philosophy and
the Mirror of Nature,
________ (1991) Consequences of
Pragmatism, Harvester Wheatsheaf,
Schacht, Richard (1995) Making Sense
of Nietzsche: Reflections Timely and Untimely,
Williams, Michael (1991) Unnatural
Doubts: Epistemological Realism and the Basis of Scepticism, Blackwell,
___________ (1993) “Realism and
Scepticism” in John Haldane and Crispin Wright eds. Reality, Representation
and Projection,
[1] It has become standard in Nietzsche studies
to comment on the textual issue in order to justify one’s use of particular texts
from amongst Nietzsche’s corpus of writings. A complete discussion of the
textual issue is beyond the scope of the present analysis. However, I shall
focus principally on Nietzsche’s “mature” writings from Human, All Too Human as it is arguably from this point onwards that
Nietzsche explicitly states that the thing-in-itself cannot play a role in our
knowledge. The reader should also note that I will appeal to some passages from
Nietzsche’s Nachlass. I concur with
Richard Schacht when he describes the Nachlass
as the workshop of Nietzsche’s published writings. On this basis, it seems to
me that cautious reference to these notes is justified to the extent that they
shed light on Nietzsche’s published writings. See Richard Schacht, Making Sense of Nietzsche: reflections
Timely and Untimely, (Chicago: University of Illinois Press, 1995), pp.
118-119.
[2] Thus, for example, our commonsense
discourse of middle-sized objects is arguably not globally false. Our
commonsense discourse is, however, a more narrow perspective, in Nietzsche’s
view, than that which describes those objects more comprehensively as
hierarchical organizations of force-wills. The reason that the latter
perspective is more comprehensive, for Nietzsche, is that it has, in his view,
explanatory scope across both the human and the natural sciences. For an
interesting discussion of Nietzsche’s will to power thesis as a doctrine of the
unity of the sciences see R. Lanier Anderson, “Nietzsche’s Will to Power as a
Doctrine of the Unity of Science”, in Studies
in History and Philosophy of Science, Volume 25, 1994.
[3] See, for example, On the Genealogy of Morality, III, 24.
[4] Peter Poellner emphasizes Nietzsche’s
sceptical views in Nietzsche and
Metaphysics, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995). Maudemarie Clark sees him as
a non-sceptic in Nietzsche on Truth and
Philosophy, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990).
[5] I borrow this term from Maudemarie Clark.
Other commentators such as David Owen in Nietzsche,
Politics and Modernity, (London: Sage Publications, 1995) and Aaron Ridley,
Nietzsche’s Conscience, (London:
Cornell University Press, 1998) have also used it. As will be seen, I employ
this term in a specifically epistemic sense.
[6] It may be thought that Nietzsche’s view
that reality is ultimately will to power does little to avoid this dilemma for
it creates a picture of reality that is alien to our commonsense view. However,
this is arguably not the case if we understand the will to power as an explanation of our commonsense reality. Explanations
involve going beyond the thing that requires explanation. Otherwise we would
merely appeal to the very thing that requires explanation as an explanation.
This is precisely what Nietzsche criticizes as “simply repeating the question”
in Beyond Good and Evil, 11.
[7] What I call “metaphysical realism” here is
similar to what Michael Williams calls “epistemic realism” in Unnatural Doubts. I follow Maudemarie
Clark in using the term “metaphysical realism”, however, because it captures
Nietzsche’s view that the epistemological issues of truth and justification
have been intertwined with dualist metaphysics throughout the history of
philosophy.
[8] As I am concerned to outline Nietzsche’s
dissatisfaction with metaphysical realism, I am interested in Kant’s philosophy
here only to the extent that it makes manifest Nietzsche’s contention with this
world-view. I will therefore refrain from commenting on the accuracy of this
particular, historically-rooted, interpretation of Kant.
[9] I have borrowed this term from Michael
Williams, “Realism and Scepticism” in John Haldane and Crispin Wright eds. Reality, Representation and Projection, (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1993), pp. 193-215.
[10] This is not to suggest, however, that
Nietzsche thinks that our in principle best-justified beliefs are “mere”
perspectives. For it is clear from some of his comments, for example, on
Christianity, that he thinks that some perspectives are better, in the sense of
being more justified, than others. See, for example, The Gay Science, 151.
[11] The distinction between cognitive
capacities and interests is to be understood here as a distinction between the
acquisition of knowledge and the justification of knowledge respectively. For a
discussion of these issues see Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1996), chapter 4.
[12] Nietzsche’s appeal to certainty here is
not an appeal to dogmatic or unrevisable truth. Rather, the quest for certainty
of which Nietzsche speaks pertains to the quest for the best reasons in support
of a belief. In The Gay Science, 319
Nietzsche again insists on “intellectual conscience” and the need to
“scrutinize our experiences as severely as a scientific experiment”.
[13]
[14] Nietzsche rejects subjective idealism in Beyond Good and Evil, 15. He writes at Beyond
Good and Evil, 36 that “I do not mean the material world as a delusion, as
‘appearance’ or ‘representation’ (in the Berkeleian or Schopenhauerian sense),
but rather as a world with the same level of reality that our emotion has”
–”
[15] See Peter Poellner, Nietzsche and Metaphysics, pp. 33-4.
[16] Brian Leiter attributes a similar position
to Nietzsche in “Perspectivism in Nietzsche’s Genealogy of Morals” in Richard Schacht ed. Nietzsche, Genealogy, Morality, (London: University of California
Press, 1994), p. 350.
Copyright © 2005 Minerva
All rights are reserved, but
fair and good faith use with full attribution may be made of this work for
educational or scholarly purposes.
Dr. Tsarina
Doyle completed her PhD at the
Return to Minerva (Volume 9) Main Page
Go to Top of This Page