ISSN
1393-614X Minerva - An Internet Journal of Philosophy Vol. 8 2004.
____________________________________________________
ARISTOTLE’S
RHETORIC AND THE COGNITION OF BEING: HUMAN EMOTIONS AND THE
RATIONAL-IRRATIONAL DIALECTIC
Brian
Ogren |
Abstract
Within the second book of his Rhetoric, intent upon the art of persuasion, Aristotle sets forth
the earliest known methodical explication of human emotions. This placement
seems rather peculiar, given the importance of emotional dispositions in both Aristotle’s
theory of moral virtues and in his moral psychology. One would expect to find a
full account of the emotions in his extensive treatment of virtues as it
appears in his ethical treatises, or as part of his psychological system in De Anima. In none of these places,
however, does a systematic treatment of this part of Aristotle’s psychology
emerge as it does in the Rhetoric.
Such is a surprising, seemingly unusual phenomenon in consideration of
Aristotle’s extreme care for and obsession with organization and
categorization.
Earnest analysis, however, reveals the intricate
ingeniousness of Aristotle’s innovative project. Emotion, based upon the
interplay between what Aristotle deems to be the ‘uniquely human’ rational and
irrational parts of the human soul, involves Being and Being’s cognition of
itself, and its dialectical encounter with the faculty of pure reason. Within
this encounter is born human emotion.
According to this formula, emotion is a phenomenon
that is linked to concrete human existence while at the same time being
fundamentally involved with cognition. Emotion bridges the gap between the
this-worldliness of the human and his keen logic as a rational being. Such an
understanding allows Aristotle to assert that emotional appeal, which often
stands at the core of rhetoric, is not necessarily a way of tricking people or
avoiding critical response, but can be used to persuade by bringing facts to
people’s awareness. Through his novel rhetoric of emotion, Aristotle not only
sheds light on the human condition, he brings rhetoric itself into the realm of
the rational and the valid as a suitable means of human discourse.
It
is not an accident that the earliest systematic Interpretation of affects that
has come down to us is not treated in the framework of ‘psychology.’ Aristotle
investigates the pathe [affects] in the second book of his Rhetoric. Contrary to the traditional
orientation, this work of Aristotle must be taken as the first systematic
hermeneutic of the everydayness of Being with one another. Publicness, as the
kind of Being which belongs to the ‘they’ not only has in general its own way
of having a mood, but needs moods and ‘makes’ them for itself. It is into such
a mood and out of such a mood that the orator speaks. He must understand the
possibilities of moods in order to rouse them and guide them aright.
(Heidegger, p. 178.)
Aristotle’s Rhetoric
contains the earliest known systematic account of what the Greeks called pathe,
that aspect of psychology involving emotions and their influences upon human
judgement. Within this systematic account, Aristotle does not only explicate,
compare and contrast various emotions, he also characterizes emotions
themselves. “The emotions [pathe],” he writes, “are those things through
which, by undergoing change, people come to differ in their judgements and
which are accompanied by pain and pleasure, for example, anger, pity, fear, and
other such things and their opposites” (1991 p. 121). He goes on to explain in
an explicit manner his method of expounding the emotions, stating the need to
divide the discussion of each emotion into three headings; these are the state
of mind of the person experiencing the emotion, against whom the
emotion is felt, and for what reasons an emotion may have arisen. All
three of these headings, according to Aristotle, are necessary for the creation
in someone of an emotion that might sway judgement. Such is the structure from
which Aristotle seeks to complete his theory on the emotions by setting up “a
list of propositions [protaseis]”(1991, p. 121) concerning each
individual emotion.
Aristotle’s systematic framework for the explication of the
emotions within the Rhetoric provokes
a number of questions and thoughts. First of all, it seems rather peculiar,
given the importance of emotional dispositions in both Aristotle’s theory of
moral virtues and in his moral psychology, that the fullest account of the
emotions would present itself in the Rhetoric.
This is especially the case since, in Aristotle’s schema, “the non-rational
part of the soul whose virtues are the virtues of character can be regarded as
primarily the seat of the emotions” (Striker, p. 286). As such, one would
expect to find a full account of the emotions in Aristotle’s extensive
treatment of virtues as it appears in his ethical treatises. In a like manner,
as an indispensable element of the non-rational part of the soul, one could
anticipate an extensive explication of the emotions in his work on the soul, De Anima. In none of these places
however, does a systematic treatment of this part of Aristotle’s psychology
emerge as it does in the Rhetoric. At
first glance, this might seem peculiar since the Rhetoric is a work that is not primarily concerned with virtue or
psychology, but with the proper means of persuasion. Such is a surprising,
seemingly unusual phenomenon in consideration of Aristotle’s extreme care for
and obsession with organization and categorization, and inexorably raises the
question as to why Aristotle chose to offer an extensive theory of the emotions
within this forum as opposed to any other.
When the detailed elucidation of emotions does appear in the Rhetoric, the examples given, with a few
exceptions, are not drawn from rhetorical situations. To cite an instance,
Aristotle claims that people become angry at those who speak against and deride
things which they themselves pride and take seriously. “For example,” he writes
in the Rhetoric, “those taking pride
in philosophy if someone speaks against philosophy or taking pride in their
appearance if someone attacks their appearance” (p.128) will become angry.
Neither the anger associated with pride in philosophy nor the anger associated
with pride in appearance relates in any way to a rhetorical situation. As such,
Aristotle seems to be deviating from rhetorical discourse. Furthermore, some of
Aristotle’s examples of emotional states not only derive from non-rhetorical
situations, they do not at all even fit a deliberative, judicial, or epideictic
audience (1991, p. 122). Concerning anger, for example, Aristotle writes in the
Rhetoric,
Those
who are ill, in need of money, [in the middle of a battle], in love, thirsty —
in general those longing for something and not getting it — are irascible and
easily stirred to anger, especially against those belittling their present
condition; for example, one who is ill [is easily stirred to anger] by things
related to his sickness, one who is in need by things related to his poverty,
one at war by things related to the war, one in love by things related to his
love, and similarly also in the other cases; for each has prepared a path for
his own anger because of some underlying emotion (pp. 127-128).
None of the persons mentioned in this example are at all likely
to constitute the audience for any type of public address, be it deliberative,
judicial, or epideictic; therefore this type of situation should be of no
concern to the rhetorician. Aristotle seems to have failed to adopt his
examples of emotional states to the art of oratory persuasion. Consequentially,
many consider the propositions concerning the emotions that come into view in
chapters two through eleven of the Rhetoric
to be part of a philosophical work that was later added and only partially
adapted to the needs of a speaker.
Aristotle’s explicit use of the word “propositions” [protaseis]
concerning the emotions led Grimaldi to propose that the discourse on the
emotions was not a later addition of an obscure philosophical passage but
rather a carefully construed preparation of premises for enthymemes. Jakob
Wisse objects to this view (pp. 20-29), stating that if this indeed were
Aristotle’s aim, he would have done considerably more to make it clear.
Furthermore, he would not have expressly enjoined in book three of the Rhetoric, “When you would create pathos,
do not speak in enthymemes; for the enthymeme either knocks out the pathos or
is spoken in vain (p. 274).” Aristotle holds enthymemes to be too coldly
logical to evoke the arousal of emotion and as such, sees them as either
overshadowing any such arousal or simply standing as superfluous to it. As
forms of syllogism based on endoxa, enthymemes cannot possibly come into direct
contact with emotions, which reside in the part of the soul that Aristotle
considers to be essentially a-rational. Thus, Aristotle’s primary goal in
presenting a systematic account of the emotions in his discourse on Rhetoric cannot logically be the
foundation for enthymemes or any other purpose of logical persuasion. Rather,
Aristotle’s discourse on the emotions appears to be for the provision of a
speaker with the ability to persuade an audience in a manner entirely different
than anything rational, namely, through the arousal of emotions in the
inherently a-rational faculty of the soul.
In full accord with his two means of persuasion within the Rhetoric, namely, the enthememe and the
arousal of emotion, Aristotle suggests two parts of the human soul that are
equally unique to the human composition, namely, a rational capacity and an
a-rational element. After going through a distillation process of the uniquely
human parts of the soul in the Nicomachean
Ethics, Aristotle explains that “one element in the [human] soul is
irrational and one has a rational principle (p. 25).” He holds the rational
faculty to be categorically unique to the human condition, whereas he divides
the irrational faculty into further components. Of these components of the
irrational faculty, one is shared by all forms of life while the other is uniquely
human in character. Further along in the
Nicomachean Ethics, he clarifies, “Of
the irrational element one division seems to be widely distributed, and
vegetative in its nature, I mean that which causes nutrition and growth (p.
25).” This division “has by its nature no share in human excellence” (p. 26),
whereas its counterpart is as uniquely human as the rational principle. Here,
Aristotle is developing a human psychology that incorporates an irrational yet
no less wholly human element into the process of human growth and
understanding. The recognition and explication of a uniquely human
irrationality gives Aristotle room to develop his methodological theory of the
emotions in the Rhetoric as an affect
of judgement separate from yet no less powerful than persuasion through logical
means.
Before explicating the uniquely human component of the
irrational part of the soul which stands as the ground of the emotions, it is
of fundamental importance to understand Aristotle’s usage of the term
‘irrational.’ Inasmuch as Aristotle explains the ‘irrational’ part of the soul
to include that part which is vegetative by nature, his use of the term
‘irrational’ in this context cannot be taken as pejorative. As Bryan Register
has pointed out, the word ‘irrational’ is usually understood to mean “something
which, having had the chance to be rational, failed to take the opportunity”
(p. 8). Hence, a serial killer is considered to be irrational while an
earthquake is not. Nor can a tree, a flower, a dog, or any other living thing
without a rational faculty but with a nutritive faculty be considered
irrational under the conventional usage of the term. Correspondingly,
Aristotle’s distinction of the ‘irrational,’ vegetative part of the human soul
involves neither the capability of rationality nor the defective quality of the
standard understanding of irrationality that arises from the failure to seize
that capability. ‘Irrational’ in this case cannot be taken to imply something
that is illogical or unreasonable, and by association, Aristotle’s ‘irrational’
seat of the emotions within the irrational part of the human soul is no less
depreciative than his ‘rational’ seat of the enthymeme. Consequently,
Aristotle’s ‘irrational’ part of the human soul, which contains neither a lack nor
a deficiency of rationality, is simply ‘a-rational,’ i.e., wholly other than
anything rational.
Aristotle considers the “rational principle” to be the only
thing that is “peculiar to man” (1969 p. 13), and therefore, that part of the
irrational component of the soul which is peculiar to man alone would seemingly
be unable to be something that is wholly other than anything rational. Indeed,
Aristotle asserts that as opposed to the categorically irrational vegetative
part of the soul, there exists as peculiar to the human being “another
irrational element in the soul – one which in a sense, however, shares in a
rational principle” (1969 p. 26). Aristotle seems to have cornered himself into
a paradox by insisting that rationality is the only feature unique to humanity
while at the same time asserting that there exists a uniquely human component
within the irrational part of the soul. How can something that is rational be
part of something that is a-rational, and how can something that is a-rational
consist of something that is rational? The assertion of such a proposition
itself seems to be utterly irrational.
David Ross has tried to resolve this apparent contradiction
by focusing on Aristotle’s statement that “the vegetative element (i.e., the
one shared by all living creatures) in no way shares in a rational principle,
but the appetitive and in general the desiring element (i.e., the one specific
to human beings) in a sense shares in it, in so far as it listens to and obeys
it” (1969 p. 27). The idea, as stated by Ross in a footnote to his translation
of the Nicomachean Ethics, is that
the uniquely human faculty of desire can be said to “share in a rational
principle” insofar as it is obedient to reason; it is in itself not a reasoning
function and in no way can originate rationality. In such a manner, this part
of the soul is uniquely human in that it participates in the uniquely human
trait of rationality and at the same time is wholly a-rational in that it holds
nothing intrinsically rational.
Ross sees Aristotle’s next sentence as an analogy that seems
to support his reading of Aristotle’s theory of the rationality of the
irrational part of the soul as being rational through the means of obedience
alone. In this next sentence of the Nichomachean
Ethics, Aristotle states that the acquiescence of the desiring element of
the soul to rationality is “the sense in which we speak of ‘taking account’ of
one’s father or one’s friends, not that in which we speak of ‘accounting’ for a
mathematical property” (p. 27). “Taking account” of one’s father or one’s
friends advice requires no origination of cognition, but rather a passive
acceptance and ordering of something provided by an outside cognitive source.
“Accounting for” a mathematical property, on the other hand, requires an
original seat of cognition. Likewise, the desiring part of the irrational mind
is not in itself rational but allows itself to be ordered by the uniquely human
rational part of the soul, thereby taking part in an activity which is uniquely
human. Through obedience alone, this irrational part of the human soul can
share in rationality while remaining wholly irrational intrinsically.
Ross’s reading of Aristotle, as followed by other
commentators such as Stephen R. Leighton, does not allow the ‘irrational’
rationality of Aristotle to take on a form and to stand apart from the purely
rational part of the soul. Rather, this reading reduces Aristotle’s idea of the
uniquely human ‘irrational’ element that shares in rationality to the
perceptual level of something that affects perception, rather than viewing it
on the epistemic level of something that affects beliefs and knowledge.
According to this view, the desiring part of the irrational mind, along with
its associate ‘emotion,’ as stated by Leighton, “is meant to alter perception
through the expectation of emotion and the ‘putting together’ (suntithemenon)
of things accordingly” (p. 213). This part of the soul simply receives
information and orders it.
Stephen Leighton tries to make sense of the idea that the
uniquely human irrational element is a means of perception by referring to
Aristotle’s distinction in De Anima
2.6 of objects of perception per se and objects of perception per
accidens. An object of perception per se is an object of perception
in itself; an object of perception per accidens is an object of
perception through the medium of associative ordering. Leighton explains the
distinction in the following way:
Suppose
that the object of perception that we all are seeing (the object per se)
is a black, circular, flat thing. If it is a record, a piece of plastic, and
something else as well, then according to Aristotle, those latter things are
perceived per accidens, even though particular perceivers may not
perceive it as those things and they may not, therefore, be “their object.”
Although with my knowledge of records what I perceive it as is a record, and
with another’s knowledge of the mysteries of Lil, what she or he perceives it
as is the sacred God, and so on, still what is perceived per accidens is
the record and the sacred God. While what is seen per se and even per
accidens remains the same, the object per accidens that it is
perceived as need not be the same for the devotee in Lil and myself. We can say
“our objects” are different (p. 214).
Different people seeing the same thing per se may see
different things per accidens. What is seen per accidens depends
on purely subjective experience, expectation and associative ordering; any
logic that might be involved is not intrinsic but is by the allowance of
experience and association alone. Such a framework, which does not necessitate
logic, can easily lead to error and misperception based on false associations
and mistaken ordering.
Objects of perception per accidens act as the cornerstone
of the uniquely human irrational element of the soul, which is the seat of the
emotions. Thus, the element of the human soul which encompasses the faculty of
emotion is, as Leighton puts it, “supposed to be part of our way of viewing the
world. Our way of viewing the world, is the way we put things together, and
thus brings about an alteration of perception” (p. 215). As based on objects of
perception per accidens, this uniquely human irrational element of the
soul is highly susceptible to error and is therefore properly deemed to be
‘irrational.’ It can, however, be persuaded by the rational principle through
its natural process of association and ordering. In such a manner, it can avoid
all error and can lead to an understanding of the truth. Hence Aristotle can
claim that this “element in a sense shares in” the rational principle, but only
“insofar as it listens to and obeys it” (1969 p. 27). As the only irrational
element capable of listening to and obeying rationality, this desiring element
can be said to remain wholly irrational in itself while at the same time, to
the extent of its obedience, can share in rationality. The capability of
listening to and obeying rationality alone, even if it does not do so, makes
this desiring element uniquely human.
Ross, furthered by Leighton, presents a very strong and
convincing reading of Aristotle’s concept of irrational human desire as a
wholly irrational element that shares in rationality only to the extent that it
acquiesces to the purely rational element of the human soul. Nevertheless, this
reading possesses a flaw, in that in order for an element to be able to accept,
and even more so to be able to order principles of rationality, that element
must have some intrinsic capacity for rationality. The acceptance and ordering
of principles of rationality cannot possibly be purely subjective and
arbitrary, especially if the element is to share in the principles of
rationality through this acceptance and ordering. In terms of Aristotle’s own
analogy, in order to “take account” of the advice of one’s father or one’s
friends, one must have some cognition of that advice. One does not blindly
absorb advice like a sponge that absorbs water, but rather must first
comprehend the advice and then must use some type of cognition in order to
apply it. This is a much different type of cognition than that of the
originator of the advice, but it is nevertheless an intrinsically cognitive
type of discernment.
Aristotle asserts this intrinsic type of cognition within the
uniquely human irrational part of the soul by affirming that the giving of
advice involves “reproof and exhortation” (1969 p. 27). Neither reproof nor
exhortation would be necessary on the part of the advisor if the advisee were
purely passive. Notwithstanding, due to an inherent, albeit different form of
rationality on the part of the advisee, the advisor necessitates the use of
persuasion. Applying the analogy to the principle being explicated by
Aristotle, the irrationally desiring part of the human soul that encompasses
the emotions possesses a form of cognition which is much different than that
found in the wholly rational part of the soul, but which is nonetheless
inherent to it. Without this inherent rationality, it would be impossible for
this element to absorb and to order principles of rationality. With this
inherent rationality, this irrational element can interact with and be
persuaded by that uniquely human element which is pure rationality.
According to Ross, the term used by Aristotle to mean “take
account of” and “account for” within his illustrating analogy of advice also
means “to have a rational principle” (p. 27). As such, Aristotle’s analogy
could also possibly read that the sharing of the irrational element in a
rational principle “is the sense in which we speak of ‘having a rational
principle’ [in terms] of one’s father or one’s friends [i.e., their advice],
not that in which we speak of ‘having a rational principle’ [in terms] of a
mathematical property” (p. 27). Such a reading supports the idea that Aristotle
holds rationality to be a complex, uniquely human system that encompasses two
separate yet related forms of cognition. One of these is pure, absolute
rationality in the sense of the rules of formal logic. The other, which
contains the emotional faculty, is fundamentally associated with human
existence, or Being in the world, and the human’s awareness thereof. This
‘irrational’ form of rationality does not categorically follow the rules of
formal logic, but as an awareness of human ‘Being,’ is fully aware of that
uniquely human element of the soul which is rationally commensurate to formal
logic. As such, this ‘irrational’ form of rationality stands apart from that
pure element of rationality which is formal logic while, at the same time, it
can be influenced and persuaded by it through the means of “reproof and
exhortation.” It can also share in the rational principle even though it is not
itself pure rationality, but only “in so far as it listens to and obeys” this
principle.
Included in the fundamentally irrational rational part of the
human soul is “the appetitive and in general the desiring element” (Aristotle
1969 pp. 29-31), which is essential to human vitality and development. Inasmuch
as it is the desiring part of the soul, this appetitive mental function
necessarily involves the sensations of pleasure and pain. As Aristotle writes
in his ethical treatises,
Pleasure
[and as a corollary, the avoidance of pain, which is antithetical to pleasure]
is naturally desirable, because it perfects our energies, that is our life, in
the continuance of which all delight. But whether life is desired for the sake
of pleasure, or pleasure for the sake of life, needs not at present be
examined; since these two seem so intimately combined as not to admit of
separation. Pleasure, then, cannot exist without energy; and our energies are
strengthened and perfected by the pleasures accompanying them (p. 356).
Appetite involves desire and by extension involves
pleasure, since pleasure “is naturally desirable.” All of these involve the
strengthening and perfection of energy, and as such are indispensable to human
life.
Aristotle seems here to be positing a uniquely human
mental function which is similar to, yet distinct from animal appetite. This
function’s similarity to animal appetite comes by way of its pursuit of
pleasure as a quest intricately related to its life-force. Aristotle allows for
a general animalistic desire for pleasure, stating that “Eudoxus thought
pleasure the chief good, because he perceived it to be universally desired by
all animals, rational and irrational.” Aristotle gives credibility to Eudoxus’s
argument of the shared desire for pleasure by humans and animals by asserting
that Eudoxus confirmed his argument “by considering pain, which, being the
contrary to pleasure, all animals endeavoured to shun and escape.” Humans and
animals share the desire for pleasure and the endeavor to shun pain, which
makes the distinctively human irrational similar to animal appetite.
The humanly rational-irrational
faculty’s distinction from mere animal appetite lies in its awareness of itself
through its awareness of its object; this takes place by way of its intricate
connection with the ‘premise of the good’ as related to the sensations of pleasure
and pain. Pleasure and pain, as affiliates of appetite and desire, which are
necessary for human nutrition and growth, are fundamentally involved in the
human being’s pursuit of goals that are essential for his or her subsistence.
Consequently, when Aristotle insists in the Rhetoric
that emotions involve pleasure and pain in his assertion that “the emotions [pathe]
are those things … which are accompanied by pain and pleasure, for
example, anger, pity, fear, and other such things and their opposites” (p.
121), he is linking the emotions to motivation and human functionality.
Pain and pleasure are a part of the
concept of any given emotion, and neither can be separated from the emotion.
Since pain and pleasure are correlates of appetite and desire, then by logical
extension, emotions necessarily involve appetite and desire. “Emotion is a subclass of orexis,”
writes Martha Craven Nussbaum, commenting upon Aristotle, orexis being
“a reaching out, or desire,” which supplies the human being with a “premise of
the good” (pp. 304, 306). This “premise of the good” comes by way of the
uniquely human irrational faculty’s awareness of itself through an awareness of
its object of desire. As Nussbaum asserts, “Even the bodily appetites — hunger, thirst, sexual
desire — are seen by
Aristotle as forms of intentional awareness, containing a view of their
object” (p. 304). When applied to the emotional faculty, this intentional
awareness that contains a view of its object ultimately culminates in a
reflexive view of itself as triggered by thoughts of its object. This point can
be elucidated in reference to Aristotle’s definition of ‘anger’ as set forth in
the second book of the Rhetoric.
Aristotle defines anger as a desire for
revenge accompanied by pain because of an apparently unjustified slight that
was directed to oneself or to those near to one (1991, p. 124). According to
this definition, anger necessarily involves an object that has caused the anger
and to which the anger is directed. Moreover, according to Fortenbaugh, anger
necessarily involves the thought of outrage, “so that such a thought is
mentioned in the essential definition of anger” (p. 12). Similarly, fear
involves the necessary thought of a “future destructive or painful evil”
(Aristotle 1991, p. 139), and pity necessarily involves the thought “that some
evil is actually present of the sort that he [i.e., the one who pities] or one
of his own [one of the pitier’s own] might suffer” (p. 152). By definition, emotions
involve cognition and reflexive thought as part of their definition. Aristotle casts emotion as a complex
phenomenon which necessarily involves not only a painful or a pleasurable
stimulus by an outside object, but also reflexive thought as stirred by that
stimulus.
Aristotle’s analysis of emotions is an inclusive analysis
that places the emotional faculty within the framework of the uniquely human
‘irrational’ element of the soul that “in a sense shares in a rational
principle” (1969, p. 27). As a complex phenomenon that makes room for a variety
of items within its essential definition, the human irrational element is, in
essence, the predication of a uniquely human hermeneutic element that
a-rationally starts from human ‘Being’ and this ‘Being’s’ cognition of itself.
Such perspicacious insight into human understanding intrinsically links
cognitive phenomena to concrete, physical being. Such is not such a stretch for
one who was as obsessed with biology and physics as he was with metaphysics, and
who saw the soul as almost completely associated with the body. This
association gives Aristotle a whole new platform from which to champion emotion
as a phenomenon that is linked to concrete human existence while at the same
time being fundamentally involved with cognition. This keen acumen allows
Aristotle to assert that the emotional appeal, which often stands at the core
of rhetoric, is not necessarily a way of tricking people or avoiding critical
response, “but can be a way of bringing facts to people’s awareness and
providing individuals with rational motivations” (Register, p. 5). Due to the
uniquely human hermeneutic element of the soul which is the conjunction of
‘Being’ with the ‘cognition of Being,’ Emotion stands on equal grounds as the
enthememe as one validly available means of rhetorical persuasion.
Commenting upon the rhetoric of discourse, Hayden White
pronounces that “discourse itself, the verbal operation by which the
questioning consciousness situates its own efforts to bring a problematical
domain of experience under cognitive control, can be defined as a movement
through all of the structures of relating self to other which remain
implicit as different ways of knowing the fully matured consciousness” (pp.
10-11). For Aristotle, emotion, as well as enthememe, acts as one of these
structures of discourse. Under the structure of the enthememe, rhetoric finds
itself amenable to the discourse of reason based on popular opinion. Under the
structure of human consciousness as a whole, “the rhetorical situations in
which we find ourselves are defined by an emotional urgency that calls for a
response” (Scult, p. 8). In both cases, rhetoric can be understood as the
communication of ideas to the masses and the suasion of the masses into action
through the communication of those very ideas. This formulation has allowed
Martin Heidegger, commenting upon Aristotle’s Rhetoric, to state, “Rhetoric [as understood by Aristotle] is
nothing other than the interpretation of concrete Dasein, the
hermeneutic of Dasein itself” (quoted in Scult, p. 3). Aristotle’s
formulation of rhetoric involves an attempt at an understanding of the human’s
understanding of his or her own concrete situation in the world.
Despite his rigid hierarchies of categories of knowledge and
his consistent obsession with paradigms of intellection, Aristotle did accept
modes of understanding other than formal logic. This is best evinced in his
theory of the emotions as outlined in his Rhetoric.
Prior to Aristotle, emotion was viewed as an entity “naturally opposed to
reason and conceived of as something hostile to thoughtful judgement. It was
Aristotle’s contribution,” according to Fortenbaugh, “to offer a very different
view of emotion, so that emotional appeal would no longer be viewed as an extra-rational
enchantment” (p. 18). Aristotle effected such a change in two ways. First of
all, he emphasized the cognitive side of emotional response. By construing
thought as a necessary condition of emotion, he showed that emotional response
is intelligent behaviour based in human cognition; though not following the
strict laws of formal logic, thought, as a necessary condition, opens emotion
up to reason. Secondly, Aristotle based his theory of the emotions upon the
uniquely human irrational part of the soul. As a part of the soul that is aware
of its concrete existence, the uniquely human irrational as formulated by
Aristotle gave him a platform from which to exposit emotion as a uniquely human
complex that is simultaneously linked to the concrete and the cognitive.
Aristotle’s project not only brought rhetoric as based on emotion into the
realm of the reasonable, it opened up the circle of the reasonable to include
an alternative form of perception and consciousness. This provided a model and
a strong foundation for subsequent thinkers to reconsider paradigms of both
thought and rhetoric in the perpetual quest to reconcile the rational with the
concrete.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Aristotle. (1893) Aristotle’s Ethics. Translated by John
Gillies. London, George Routledge and Sons.
Aristotle. (1991) On Rhetoric: A Theory of Civic Discourse. Translated by George A. Kennedy. New York, Oxford University Press.
Aristotle. (1969) The Nicomachean Ethics. Translated by
David Ross. London, Oxford
University Press.
Fortenbaugh, William W.
(1975) Aristotle on Emotion. London,
Gerald Duckworth and
Company.
Heidegger, Martin. (1962) Being and Time. Translated by John
Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. San Francisco, Harper and Row.
Leighton, Stephen R. (1996) “Aristotle
and the Emotions.” In Rorty, Amelie Oksenberg (ed.) Essays on Aristotle’s Rhetoric. Berkeley, University of California
Press. pp. 206-237.
Nussbaum, Martha Craven.
(1996) “Aristotle on Emotions and Rational Persuasion.” In Rorty, Amelie Oksenberg
(ed.) Essays on Aristotle’s Rhetoric.
Berkeley, University of California Press. pp. 303-323.
Register, Bryan. (1999) The Logic and Validity of Emotional Appeal
in Classical Greek Rhetorical Theory. University of Texas at Austin, May.
Scult, Allen. (1999)
“Aristotle’s Rhetoric as Ontology: A Heideggerian Reading.” Philosophy and Rhetoric. 32.2 (1999)
Pennsylvania, Pennsylvania State University Press.
Striker, Gisela. (1996)
“Emotions in Context: Aristotle’s Treatment of the Passions in the Rhetoric
and His Moral Psychology.” In Rorty, Amelie Oksenberg (ed.) Essays on Aristotle’s Rhetoric.
Berkeley, University of California Press. pp. 286-302.
White, Hayden. (1978) Tropics of Discourse: Essays in Cultural
Criticism. Baltimore, Johns Hopkins University Press.
Wisse, Jakob. (1989) Ethos and Pathos from Aristotle to Cicero.
Amsterdam, Hakkert.
Copyright © 2004 Minerva
All rights are reserved, but fair and good faith use with full attribution may
be made of this work for educational or scholarly purposes.
Brian Ogren is a doctoral candidate in the department
of Jewish Thought at the Hebrew University of Jerusalem in Israel, where he
teaches and does research in the areas of Jewish philosophy and mysticism. His
doctoral dissertation centers around the concept of metempsychosis in Italian
Jewish thought. Return to Minerva (Volume 8) Main
Page
Go to Top of This Page