ISSN 1393-614X Minerva
- An Internet Journal of Philosophy Vol. 11 2007
________________________________________________
The Unlimited
Responsibility of Spilling Ink Marko Zlomislic |
Abstract
In order
to show that both Derrida’s epistemology and his ethics can be understood in
terms of his logic of writing and giving, I consider his conversation with
Searle in Limited Inc. I bring out
how a deconstruction that is implied by the dissemination of writing and giving
makes a difference that accounts for the creative and responsible decisions
that undecidability makes possible. Limited
Inc has four parts and I will interpret it in terms of the four main
concepts of Derrida. I will relate signature, event, context to Derrida’s
notion of dissemination and show how he differs from Austin and Searle
concerning the notion of the signature of the one who writes and gives.
Next, I will show how in his reply to Derrida,
entitled, “Reiterating the Differences”, Searle overlooks Derrida’s thought
about the communication of intended meaning that has to do with Derrida’s
distinction between force and meaning and his notion of differance. Here I will show that Searle cannot even follow his own
criteria for doing philosophy. Then by looking at Limited Inc, I show how Derrida differs from Searle because
repeatability is alterability. Derrida has an ethical intent all along to show
that it is the ethos of alterity that is called forth by responsibility and
accounted for by dissemination and difference.
Of course, comments on comments, criticisms of
criticisms, are subject to the law of diminishing fleas, but I think there are
here some misconceptions still to be cleared up, some of which seem to still be
prevalent in generally sensible quarters. J.L. Austin, “Unfair to Facts”
It was the project of modernity to ground ethics in epistemology. Descartes thought that if we could with our reason establish the three metaphysical roots of the tree of knowledge namely the cogito, God and matter, we could then on that foundation explain, physics, mechanics, medicine and morals.
It has been the task of all the existential-postmodernists to show that accounting for ethics within the limits of reason alone is not enough. Kierkegaard set ethics within the wider context of faith and Nietzsche within the ethos of a joyful wisdom. Derrida continues their way of accounting for ethics in terms of what he calls the gift of responsibility. He thinks that since Hegel, the logic of writing, which is also the logic of the pharmakon and the logic of the gift, has become possible. His understanding of responsibility is set in the ethos of a pre-arche writing and a pre-arche giving.
In order to show how Derrida’s epistemology and his ethics can be understood in terms of this logic of writing and giving, I will consider his conversation with Searle in Limited Inc, in order to bring out how a deconstruction that is implied by the dissemination of writing and giving makes a difference that accounts for the creative and responsible decisions that undecidability makes possible.
Limited Inc has four parts and I will interpret it in terms of the four main concepts of Derrida. That is, I will relate signature, event, and context to Derrida’s notion of dissemination and show how he differs from Austin and Searle concerning the notion of the signature of the one who writes and gives.
Secondly, I will show how in his reply to Derrida, Searle overlooks the insight about the communication of intended meaning that has to do with the distinction between force and meaning and Derrida’s notion of differance. Here I will show that Searle cannot even follow his own criteria for doing philosophy.
Next by examining Limited Inc, I will show how
Derrida differs from Searle because repeatability is alterability. This “alter”
which is in the Sanskrit word ITER is the basis for Derrida’s ethics. Both
“alter” and “iter” motivate Derrida to develop his philosophy of dissemination
and differance. Derrida has an
ethical intent all along to show that it is the ethos of alterity that is
called forth by responsibility and accounted for by dissemination and differance.
In the fourth part of this paper, I will deal with Derrida’s notion of the responsibility that governs his ethical and political thinking. I will primarily concentrate on his notion of revolutions that as yet have no model.
I Communicating the Nuclear Traits
of Writing
But I owe it to the subject to say,
that it has long afforded me what philosophy is so often thought and made
barren of- the fun of discovery, the pleasures of co-operation, and the
satisfaction of reaching agreement. J.L. Austin, “A Plea for Excuses”
One of Derrida’s first publications was a translation of Quine’s article “The Frontiers of Logical Theory”.[1] It is therefore somewhat ironic or perhaps even normal that opponents of Derrida’s writings have come from the Anglo-American analytic school of philosophy.[2] Throughout his authorship, Derrida has shown sensitivity to dimensions that the Anglo-American philosophers have overlooked or deliberately ignored. While Derrida has used the principle of charity when discussing the writings of analytic philosophers such as Quine or Searle, they have not used the same criteria when reading him.
Derrida, despite assertions to the contrary by analytic critics, does not deny the necessity of employing classical methods of textual exegesis. Derrida shows that the text does have an edge. In other words, there must be a point of departure. However, the edge, frame or center has never opened a reading. Derrida’s disconcerting law of dissemination invokes a shifting of interpretive spaces or contexts. The result is a shifting interpretive topology where philosophical, political, ethical, or religious positions no longer remain protected by the exclusionary policy of a restricted analytic economy.
Take the word, “communication” for example. In “Signature Event Context”, Derrida asks whether the word communication can communicate “an identifiable meaning, a describable value”.[3] The word communication, opens “a semantic field which precisely is not limited to semantics, semiotics, and even less to linguistics”.[4] To communicate designates the act of sharing, imparting or transmitting knowledge, information, a secret or a pleasure. To communicate is also to give or deliver over something tangible. To communicate is to participate, it is to speak or write to another; it is to join and to have in common. Derrida adds that one can communicate a movement, a tremor, and a shock or “a displacement of force”.[5] For Derrida, the literal or proper meaning is problematic because it must not be pinned down to one meaning which is what the analytic tradition wants to do. For Derrida, the issue will be the problem of polysemia and communication and dissemination.
Derrida’s insight is that the context in which a communication takes place, “is never absolutely determinable”.[6] Due to the disconcerting law of dissemination, neither context nor the event of communication can be saturated with absolute certainty. Such a stance does not imply that intelligibility, truth or meaning have been abandoned. Derrida wants to show that analytic philosophy is marked by a theoretical insufficiency when it has dealt with the notions of signature, event, and context.
The disconcerting law of dissemination displaces the concept of writing so that writing can no longer be included in the category of communication, understood solely in the restricted sense of transmitting meaning. It is self evident that writing is a means of communication “which extends very far if not infinitely, the field of oral or gestural communication”.[7] Writing understood in the usually accepted sense merely opens, “the same field to a much greater range,”[8] while remaining essentially homogeneous. According to Derrida, writing has been represented in this manner “in the entire history of philosophy”.[9] The written text of philosophy in Derrida’s view cannot be contained within a homogeneous order since whatever is written overflows and cracks its meaning. Far from leading to relativism or any sort of indeterminism, Derrida’s analyses expose the violence of the analytic limit that restricts, constricts and confines. To show the limiting character of a philosophy that designs itself to have mastered its margins requires rigorous analysis. It is through the disconcerting law of dissemination that Derrida raises the stakes of what is involved in analysis. To write otherwise is to solicit the limit, is to shake the whole and make it tremble.
Through an analysis of Condillac and Warburton, Derrida emphasizes the role that the value of absence has in their writings on communication. The value of absence “will risk introducing a certain break in the homogeneity of the system”.[10] Condillac’s notion of absence and the role it plays in communication is never fully examined by him. By taking into account the value of absence Derrida points out that, “writing no longer would be a species of communication, and all of the concepts to whose generality writing was subordinated (the concept itself as meaning, idea or grasp of meaning and idea, the concept of communication, of sign etc).”[11]Derrida gives the distinguishing features of writing given through the insights of dissemination. Derrida refers to these traits as “nuclear”. Writing breaks with the horizon of communication. The horizon of meaning is punctured by writing. Dissemination replaces polysemia as the concept of writing. Within this context, nuclear can be understood as a cluster, kernel or as the inner portion of a seed. These nuclear traits, “break with every given context, and engender infinitely new contexts in an absolutely non-saturable fashion”.[12] It is this excess without limit that can appear to generate nihilism. However, by escaping the horizon of the unity of meaning, dissemination engenders a patient, open aporetic analysis that is in constant transformation. Derrida shows how the beginning or arche of writing refers to the absences that writing makes possible. The possibility of these absences and the impossibility engendered by them is known as arche-ecriture. Writing describes the intervals between marks and their objects; between addressers and addressees.
II Announcing the Force of Truth
Here the natural economy of language operates: if the
words already available for simple cases suffice in combination to describe a
complicated case, there will be need for special reasons before a special new
word is invented for the complication. J.L. Austin, “A Plea for Excuses”
In this section I want to show that in his reply to Derrida’s “Signature,
Event, Context”, entitled “Reiterating the Differences”, John Searle misses
Derrida’s point concerning the communication of intended meanings that has to
do with Derrida’s distinction between force and meaning which is linked to his
notion of differance.
In understanding and unraveling Searle’s reading of Derrida I will follow the advice that Searle gives from his recent Mind, Language and Society: Philosophy in the Real World.[13] Searle writes,
When confronted with an intractable question such as
is presented by a clash of convictions, don’t accept the question lying down.
Get up and go behind the question to see what assumptions lie behind the
alternatives the question presents.[14]
And
The fact that there are no universally accepted
procedures for solving philosophical problems does not mean that anything goes,
that you can say anything or that there are no standards.... In philosophy
there is no substitute for a combination of original, imaginative sensibility
on the one hand, and sheer intelligent, logical rigor on the other. The rigor
without sensibility is empty, the sensibility without rigor is a lot of hot air.[15]
I will take the last quotation as an admission that Searle’s reading of Derrida is mistaken and continues to be mistaken because Searle has not followed his own criteria in dealing with “intractable questions”. Searle admits:
The methods that I employ are more adequately described,
at least in the first stages as logical or conceptual analysis. I try to find
the constitutive elements of consciousness, intentionality, speech acts and
social institutions by taking them apart and seeing how they work. But truth to
tell, even that is a distortion of the actual methodology in practice. In
practice, I use any weapon that I can lay my hands on, and I stick with any
weapon that works.[16]
So Searle admits that anything goes; that he uses “any weapon” that he can lay his hands in order to cut through philosophical problems. Searle declares that when the truth is told, there is a discrepancy between methodology and practice. Based on these admissions, it is puzzling when Searle claims in Mind, Language and Society, that he will respond, “to various aspects of the postmodern challenge”[17] to the Enlightenment.
Searle sees himself as representing the Anglo-American tradition of philosophy that responds to the “relativism” of the “collective” movement known as “postmodernism”, by making “a modest contribution to the Enlightenment vision”.[18] Perhaps such an undertaking has it merits, but Searle is mistaken when he includes Derrida among the “relativists postmoderns” without a) having carefully read Derrida’s writings, b) without giving any textual evidence of his claims and c) without engaging in a close textual analysis of Derrida’s writings (which is something one would expect a “philosopher of language” to do).
Searle believes that he is an Enlightenment realist and argues that the truth is before us in plain view and can be expressed in plain language. While defending the position that the problems of philosophy are created by philosophy itself, Searle never looks at the contesting claim that the problems noted by Derrida come out of the Enlightenment. Searle accepts Enlightenment claims to scientific certainty a priori and declares any challenge to that “optimism” such as relativity, quantum theory, Gödel’s demonstration of the incompleteness of arithmetic and Freud’s psychoanalytic discoveries as intellectually feeble and dubiously motivated.
For Derrida, writing is characterized by its force. He writes “a written sign carries with it a force of breaking with its context, that is, the set of presences which organize the moment of its inscription”.[19] It is this essential drifting that troubles Searle. For Derrida, “this force of breaking is not an accidental predicate but the very structure of the written”.[20] For Derrida, the organizational principles of unity and coherence have played an unnecessary exclusionary and repressive role in the philosophical tradition. Derrida’s work does not dispense with such classical exigencies but rather works out the theoretical and practical system of these borders.
In Derrida’s view, Searle has an unnecessary restrictive paradigm that recoils against positions that do not fit within his definition of what constitutes doing philosophy. By professing to liberate the and the force of the interrogative, Derrida frustrates inclinations to terminate the interrogative. Derrida’s writing calls us to displace the strategies of containment with the strategies of differance. Truth is an abyssal event; a folding of one mark against another mark. In contrast to the fusion desired by analytic philosophers, Derrida’s writing yields an undecidable oscillation.
To place the object of interpretation in an abyss is to generate understandings of a text that do not yield to a simple, fused horizon of meaning. Far from being a destruction of meaning, the methodology of writing en abyme, destroys the claim to unequivocal hegemony of one unified meta-narrative over another narrative. It permits multiple dimensions to interpretation.
The Anglo-American analytic tradition as represented by Searle calls for a denial of the otherness of the other; that is, a denial of alternative conceptions which fail to cohere with our own conceptual schemes. The existence of alternative conceptual schemes or worldviews is deemed incomprehensible. Unlike Searle, Austin shows a great deal of interpretive charity. In a paper entitled “A Plea for excuses” he writes, “But I owe it to the subject to say, that it has long offered me what philosophy is so often thought, and made barren of- the fun of discovery, the pleasures of co-operation and the satisfaction of reaching agreement.”[21] When asked by an interviewer from the German magazine ZIF, “So are you one of the children in the fairy tale that strip the emperor of his non-existing clothes?” Searle responds,
In some ways I like the analogy with the child that is
saying that he emperor has no clothes ... I had a similar experience when I
debated certain so-called deconstructionist philosophers such as Derrida. It
seems to me there is nothing there. It’s largely show with no underlying
substance ... the joy of philosophy comes from trying to get knowledge and
understanding of difficult areas.[22]
By way of response, a number of points (in ordinary language) can be made. First, Derrida has never claimed to be an emperor. He has never claimed to be a deconstructionist philosopher or a “so-called deconstructionist philosopher”. If Searle had read Derrida’s works, he could never claim that “there is nothing there”. In fact, there is so much in Derrida’s writings that Searle cannot comprehend the force of Derrida’s insights.[23] In other words, Searle has not attempted to understand the difficulty of Derrida’s works.
While I am in agreement with Bennington’s insight that Searle and others have given “unargued condemnations and risibly ill-informed,”[24] I want to show that there is much to be learned from Searle’s “debate” with Derrida. While I disagree with everything that Searle has written about Derrida, his article, “Reiterating the Differences” and his “Response to Derrida” in the New York Review of Books has the great merit of raising serious questions. After having studied Searle’s “reply” it is evident that Searle is misrepresenting his own problem and it must be admitted that the misrepresentation is pretty consistent.[25]
III Talking Seriously with Searle[26]
On a festive occasion you are ordered, for a forfeit,
to pretend to be a hyena: going down on all fours, you make a few essays at
hideous laughter and finally bite my calf, taking, with a touch of realism
possibly exceeding your hopes, a fair-sized piece right out of it. Beyond
question you have gone too far. (In these circumstances. But if Nero ordered
you, in the arena, to pretend to be a hyena, it might be unwisely perfunctory not to take a piece right out.) J.L.
Austin, “Pretending”.
When repeatability is seen as alterability, the alter as iter or other becomes the basis for Derrida’s ethos of alterity. Searle misses that Derrida’s ethos of alterity that is first called forth by responsibility and accounted for by dissemination and differance. Derrida writes,
Adventurous because this strategy is not a simply
strategy in the sense that strategy orients tactics according to a final goal
or telos or theme of domination, a mastery and ultimate reappropriation of the
field. Finally a strategy without finality, what might be called blind tactics
or empirical wandering if the value of empiricism did not itself acquire its
entire meaning in its opposition to philosophical responsibility.[27]
Published in 1968, the essay “Difference” exposes us to the force of Derrida’s ethical aporetic insights. To delineate differance is to give a different perspective on ethics. Differance is strategic because it is of great vital importance. It is designed to upset so called sources of political, economic, moral and theological power. The strategy of differance is not the science or art of employing military force. It is the art of deploying an ethical force.
Derrida points out that empiricism and epistemology have acquired their meaning in opposition to philosophical responsibility. Empirical, epistemological “wandering” or dissemination gives a new meaning to responsibility. Derrida views the philosophical tradition as adventurous. An adventure is an enterprise, an undertaking or a performance involving the uncertain or the unknown. Adventure signals the adventus or the arrival of the new. The word “new” can be traced back to the Latin novus and the Greek neos. The word “new” may be added to the list of Derridean undecidables such as pharmakon, supplement, trace etc. “New” means having existed or having been made but for a short time or having been seen or known but for a short time, although perhaps existing before. Derrida’s epistemology and his aporetic ethics are to be understood in terms of the new logic of writing.
The three characteristics of writing as 1. iterable, 2. a force that breaks with its contexts and 3. whose spacing permits disengagement and grafting, carries over and into Derrida’s aporetic ethics. The point of Derrida’s reply to Searle or Sarl can be summarized as follows. Searle, representing the Anglo-American analytic school of philosophy, sets up a Society with Limited Responsibility (Sociétéà Responsabilité Limitée). SARL as the self-proclaimed heir of Wittgenstein, Austin and Quine, limits and restricts the stocks of the analytic corporation residing at the University of Berkeley.[28] Derrida, however, writes that he considers himself to be in many respects quite close to Austin.
Derrida appreciates the contributions of the analytic tradition. He reads texts as iterable. The tradition is iterable. For Derrida, unlike Searle, iteration alters, something-new takes place. Sarl, the “theoretician of speech acts” has a view of writing that is narrow by confining himself to a certain interpretation of phonetic writing, indeed to the alphabetic model, to the a b c’s of logo-phonocentrism.
Searle sees Derrida’s reading of Austin as harmful and dangerous. Derrida praises speech act theory as fundamentally important and productive. Yet Searle writes, “Derrida has a distressing penchant for saying things that are obviously false”[29] Derrida’s point is that Searle’s reading of Austin is harmful. Searle’s reading of Derrida is harmful.[30] It is based on gossip, which is one form of communication to be sure, but it is not very responsible.[31]
In the collision of these positions taking place between Oxford and Paris, we are not looking for a Californian Aufhebung that would somehow reconcile Berkeley with Irvine. Given that California is the state of theory, we are not looking for a symphonic agreement aimed at finality (something that Searle wants), but a cross-cultural fecundation.[32] If one draws rigorous consequences from the insights of iterability it can deconstruct oppositional limits. The implications of iterability extend to areas such as ethics, politics, economics, etc, to transform our communicative spaces in a revolution that yet have no model.
IV Addressing the Amodal
Revolution
But whatever the defects of either of these two
movement- the ‘verification’ movement or the ‘use of language’ movement — at
any rate they have effected, nobody could deny, a great revolution in
philosophy and, many would say, the most salutary in history. (Not, if you come
to think of it, a very immodest claim). J.L. Austin, “Performative Utterances”
What are the ethical and social-political lessons to be drawn from this revolution that yet has no model? Derrida makes clear that deconstruction, as recontextualization does not amount to relativism or nihilism. Deconstruction is rooted in a given context but in one that is differentiated Derrida’s aporetic ethic is engaged in the world of context. Most commentators see relativism or nihilism in these formulations. However, Derrida sees an increase in responsibility.
How can these insights be applied? First it has to be noted that it is simply untrue that Derrida’s contribution to political thought remains as elusive as ever.[33] His early articles such as “The Ends of Man”, “Declarations of Independence”, “Nelson Mandela: In Admiration”, “Racisms Last Word” and books such as The Other Heading: Reflections on Today’s Europe, Specters of Marx, Force of Law, Politics of Friendship, Cosmopolites de tous les pays, testify to Derrida’s commitment to questions of justice. Rather than explicate all of Derrida’s texts dealing with political issues, I will only bring out those details that intersect with Searle’s concerns.
In an interview with Reason Magazine,[34] Searle gives the following insights regarding his own approach to social-political engagement: “I’ve always been active in civil liberties issues — I believe in human rights and especially the right to free speech and free expression ... this was in December of 1961 and at that point I decided this university was not deeply committed to free speech.” Searle goes on to explore Derrida’s “bad arguments” and proceeds to tell the interviewer the following incredulous account,
With Derrida you can hardly misread him, because he’s
so obscure. Every time you say, “He says so and so”, he always says, “You
misunderstand me”. But if you try to figure out the correct interpretation then
that’s not so easy. I once said this to Michel Foucault who was more hostile to
Derrida even than I am, and Foucault said that Derrida practices the method of obscurantisme terroriste (terrorism of
obscurantism). We were speaking French. And I said to Michel, “What the hell do
you mean by that?” And he said, “He writes so obscurely you can’t tell what
he’s saying, that’s the obscurantism part, and then when you criticize him, he
can always say, ‘You didn’t understand me, you’re an idiot’. That’s the
terrorism part. And I like that. So I wrote an article about Derrida. I asked
Michel if it was OK, if I quoted that passage, and he said yes.
It is difficult to know where to begin pointing out the flaws in Searle’s reading of Derrida. Given that Searle sees his philosophical work as a continuation of the Enlightenment’s scientific and philosophic program, his remarks against Derrida make any sane reader wonder which “Enlightenment” and what “program” Searle is defending? How can Searle claim to defend reason, objectivity and intellectual standards within the academy and outside of it, when his own remarks show a remarkable lack of interpretive charity? The fact that Michel Foucault may have called Derrida a terrorist that practices obscurantism only shows how low one philosopher descends when he does not allow his work to be criticized by a former student. In fact, Derrida’s criticism of Foucault’s work was so clear and distinct that Foucault could only make up ad hominem attacks. For if Derrida’s criticisms were so obscure, Foucault would not have been so badly hurt.[35]
I contend that it is Searle and not Derrida who has embraced a destructive approach, such that anything which does not fit into Searle’s definition of “philosophy” must be ridiculed and rejected before taking the time, effort and patience to understand what is being said. Searle’s position shows a contemptuous rejection of Enlightenment values. Based on his comments, his politics can only be said to be exclusionary. Searle’s attack against Derrida continued in an article entitled, “Rationality and Realism: What is at Stake?”:
To those within the
Western Rationalistic Tradition, these types of challenges have names. They are
commonly called argumentum ad hominem
and the genetic fallacy. Argumentum ad
hominem is an argument against the person who presents a view rather than
against the view itself, and the genetic fallacy is the fallacy of supposing that
because a theory one claims has a reprehensible origin, the theory or claim
itself is discredited. I hope it is obvious why anyone who accepts the idea of
objective truth and therefore objective knowledge thinks this is a fallacy and
that an argument ad hominem is an
invalid argument.[36]
The obvious question would be if Searle sees that ad hominem and genetic fallacy arguments are invalid, why does he continue to use them against Derrida? Are they valid only for Searle if and only if he is “reading” Derrida? In his “reading” of Derrida and in every public forum where Searle has been given the opportunity to criticize Derrida’s work, his arguments (sic) have made use of ad hominem, genetic fallacy and cocktail party gossip. If we use Searle’s comments against Derrida as a model then Searle destroys any legitimacy he has been given to talk about objective truth, reason and academic standards.[37] But all is not lost. There are a number of important things that a philosopher from the “continental” tradition can learn from the analytic school. For example, Bertrand Russell argues that the value of philosophy “must not depend upon any supposed body of definitely ascertainable knowledge to be acquired by those who study it. The value of philosophy is, in fact, to be sought largely in its very uncertainty.”[38] It is interesting to see Russell locating the epistemology of embracing uncertainty and making this epistemic claim into a value or moral claim. This epistemic claim of uncertainty necessitates a moral inquiry that is based on the aporia. In light of this evidence, Searle is wrong to judge Derrida when Russell makes claims that are indistinguishable from Derrida’s own.
To claim is to assent with conviction in the face of possible contradiction. To claim is also to cry out- clamare, which is also akin to calare, to call or summon. How does one begin to adjust these claims? Calare is related to the word low. To low is to call.[39] The claim that calls me takes place in the lowness of language, i.e. very close to the ground. Derrida contents that “one always works or thinks in a natural language, because therefore the absolute formalization or artificialization of language is impossible”.[40] When a complete philosophical elucidation of any language is given (as Ayer wants), and that language is formalized, analyzed and reduced to symbolic notation, what happens then?
While Ayer asserts that it is the job of philosophy to provide definitions, he warns, that “it must not be inferred that it is the function of the philosopher to compile a dictionary, in the ordinary sense”.[41] Ayer’s distinction between an explicit definition found in dictionaries and philosophical definitions of use is artificial. The nature of philosophical analysis proposed by Ayer and others, even if it adds a qualitative distinction and clears away misunderstanding in the way in which a word is used, results only in a quantitative buildup of definitions. In other words, what is the value of clearing away the ambiguity of the ambiguous word ‘is’ when there are more pressing concerns at hand? This is not to say that ordinary language analysis is without merit. Ordinary language analysis as practiced by Ayer may show how philosophers are responsible “for much of the confusion that infects their treatment of general propositions,”[42] but such a showing is without responsibility to the other. Philosophy reduced to grammar is not philosophy.
While analytic philosophers engage in questions such as whether good is defined in terms of right or right in terms of good or both in terms of value, they miss the other that calls in a cry beyond language. While Ayer asserts, “it is impossible to find a criterion for determining the validity of ethical judgements,”[43] Derrida is called a relativist for attempting to point out the relativism at work in such systems. Ayer’s relativism receives little attention from Searle, even when it is most visible in statements such as, “We find that ethical philosophy consists simply in saying that ethical concepts are pseudo-concepts and therefore unanalyzable....it appears, then, that ethics, as a branch of knowledge, is nothing more than a department of psychology and sociology.”[44] The reduction of things to linguistic problems may free us from metaphysics or even show us that “the metaphysician is a misplaced poet,”[45] but it contributes nothing to ethical, social or political questions.
Leslie Armour points out that when analyzing the human predicament, “the sum total of puzzles about value could not possibly fall before a single theory, however good it was”.[46] Armour maintains that there is a tension in the structure of experience. This tension is between the individual and the community and between the immediate and the transcendent. This tension or anxiety is at work in Derrida’s writings and a recent essay shows how this tension creates a different stance on political issues. Derrida writes,
Not only are there other ways for philosophy, but
philosophy, if there is such a thing, is the other way. And it has always been
the other way: philosophy has never been the unfolding responsible for a
unique, originary assignation linked to a unique language or to the place of a
sole people. Philosophy does not have one sole memory....We must adjust our
practice of the history of philosophy, our practice of history and
philosophy...What I am saying here of philosophy can just as well be said, and
for the same reasons of law and rights and of democracy.[47]
And
The opposition between the so-called continental
tradition of philosophy and the so-called analytic of Anglo-Saxon philosophy is
not reducible to national limits or linguistic givens. This is not only an
immense problem and an enigma for European or Anglo-American philosophers who
have been trained in these such traditions. A certain history, notably but not
only a colonial history, constituted these two models as hegemonic references
in the entire world. The right to philosophy requires not only an appropriation
of these two competing models and of almost every model by all, mean and
women...the right of all (men and women) to philosophy also requires the
reflection, the displacement and the deconstruction of these hegemonies, the
access to places and to philosophical events which are exhausted neither in
these two dominant traditions, nor in these languages.[48]
Derrida proposes the unreserved tension of competing paradigms that take place in a chiasmic communication. Such a position destroys in a constructive sense the claim to unequivocal hegemony of one tradition over other traditions. Such a stance gives an ethical account of the intolerance displayed by various interpretive communities, (i.e. Marxism, psycho-analysis, postmodernism or the tradition represented by Searle or the tradition he thinks he represents).
Derrida’s work shares affinities with W.V. Quine’s principle of the indeterminancy of translation.[49] Quine, paralleling Derrida’s statement that every reading is a new writing, contends that interpreters can develop rival, equally convincing and incompatible interpretations. While much work remains to be done to Derrida’s call for a cosmopolitical aspect of doing philosophy, Derrida’s works with the undecidable informs us that we are always already dealing with the tension of shifting interpretive topologies. In the tension of this anxiety, every reading is a new writing. Decisions must be made in the face of a series of compelling alternatives. That there is no thematic unity to resolve such interpretive rivalry places greater responsibility one who decides in a state of anxiety. This greater responsibility is brought forth through our encounter with the aporia.
What distinguishes Derrida from Searle is Derrida’s deconstruction of performative meaning. Searle wanted to legitimize performative speech acts as providing meaning, which can be used philosophically. Semiotics as the theory of signs distinguishes between syntactics, which is the relation of signs with other signs. This gives us connotational meaning. Semantics or the relation of signs with their referent gives us denotational meaning. Pragmatics or the relations of signs to their users gives us performative meaning.
What Derrida is doing is to say that philosophers have always based philosophy on the meaning of signs. Searle and the speech act theorists emphasize the performative meaning of how the sign relates to users. Derrida’s point is that no matter how many kinds of meaning or signs there are, we have to notice the force of the text and this force cannot be reduced to meaning. The distinction between force and meaning is important when Derrida deconstructs Searle. He goes from the performative meaning to the perverformative force. The simple performative cancels out the event that is full of force. The performative does not bring out the event because what is performed is limited.
The dissemination of signs gives us the force of meaning. There is an excess of signs. This force has a temporality based on differance. This brings us to deconstruction. Once we see that writing has dissemination, we see that it is in speaking as well. The written sign, the spoken sign, the conceptual sign and the transcendental signified are effected by dissemination thus making it a quasi-transcendental. Quasi-transcendental has process and relationality, which gives to it a force beyond any simple analytic meaning. Instead of this being relativism, there is an occasion to understand the leap of the decision over the abyss of undecidability. Only where there is undecidability can there be decisions.
NOTES
[1] 1. Les frontière de
la théorie logique de W.V. Quine (avec R. Martin) Études Philosophiques 2 (1964).
[2]. See Richard
Rorty’s humorous remarks in ‘Derrida and the Philosophical Tradition’ in his Truth and Progress, Philosophical Papers,
Volume 3 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991). Rorty perpetuates a
misreading of Derrida that sees him engaging in ‘jokey and raunchy
desublimizing’, 332.
[3]. Jacques Derrida
‘Signature, Event, Context’, in Margins
of Philosophy, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982), 309. Hereafter
cited as SEC (un sens identifiable, une valeur descriptible), 17. Derrida’s
reply to Searle can be found in Limited
INC, translated by Samuel Weber, (Northwestern University Press, 1988).
Searle’s reply to Derrida’s SEC was entitled, “Reiterating the differences: A reply to Derrida. Glyph 2: 198-208, 1977)
[4]. SEC,309. (ouvre
un champ sémantique qui précisément ne se limite pas à la sémantique, a la
sémiotique, encore moins a la linguistique.), 17.
[5]. SEC, 309. (un
déplacement de force.), 18.
[6]. SEC, 310. (n’est
jamais absolument déterminable.), 20.
[7]. SEC, 311. (qui étend très loin, sinon infiniment, le
champ de la communication orale ou gestuelle.), 20.
[8]. SEC, 311. (le
même champ à une très longue portée.), 21.
[9]. SEC, 311. (dans
toute l’histoire de la philosophie.), 21.
[10]. SEC,312. ( risque
d’introduire une certain rupture dans l’homogénéité du systeme.), 22.
[11]. SEC, 314-315.
(l’écriture ne serait plus une espèce de communication et tous les concepts a
la généralité desquels on subordonnait l’écriture (le concept lui-même comme
sens, idée ou saisie du sens et de l’idée, le concept de communication, de
signe, etc.), 26
[12]. SEC, 320. (rompre
avec tout contexte donné engendrer a l’infini de nouveaux contextes, de façon
absolument non-saturable.), 36.
[13]. John R. Searle, Mind, Language, Society: Philosophy in the
Real World, ( London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1999). Hereafter cited as
MLS.
[14]. MLS, 54.
[15]. MLS, 159.
[16]. MLS, 160.
[17]. MLS, 4.
[18]. MLS, 6.
[19]. SEC, 317. (une
signe écrit comporte une force de rupture avec son contexte, c’est-à-dire
l’ensemble des preéences qui organisent le moment de son inscription.) 30
[20]. SEC, 317. (Cette
force de rupture n’est pas un prédicat accidental, mais la structure même de
l’écrit.), 30.
[21]. J.L. Austin, ‘A
Plea for Excuses’, in Philosophical
Papers, (London: Oxford University Press, 1970), 175.
[22]. Ralf Stoecker,
‘Interview mit Prof. John R. Searle’, ZIF,
June 1999.
[23]. On the other
hand, Austin is very close to Derrida. In his essay, ‘Other Minds’, Austin
writes, ‘A new language is naturally necessary if we are to admit unconscious
feelings and feelings which express themselves in paradoxical manners, such as
the psycho-analysts describe’, 109. On the other hand, Austin is far from
Derrida when he believes that philosophy is something that can be overcome. In
his essay, ‘Ifs and Cans’, Austin writes, ‘Is it not possible that the next
century may see the birth, through the joint labours of philosophers,
grammarians, and numerous other students of language, of a true and
comprehensive science of language?
Then we shall have rid ourselves of one more part of philosophy (there will still
be plenty left) in the only way we can get rid of philosophy, by kicking it
upstairs’, 232.
[24]. Geoffrey
Bennington, Interrupting Derrida,
(New York: Routledge, 2000), 16. In ’Limited Think: how not to read Derrida’,
Christopher Norris argues that Derrida wins the debate, ‘not merely as a
skilful rhetorician, one who contrives to tie Searle up in philosophical knots
of his own creations, but also by far the more rigorous thinker and perceptive
exponent of Austin’s ideas’, 147. For further discussions of the Derrida-Searle
‘debate’ see Jonathan Culler, ‘Meaning and Convention: Derrida and Austin’ New Literary History, Volume 8, 1981,
5-30, and Gayatri Spivak, ‘Revolutions that as yet have no model: Derrida’s Limited Inc’, Diacritics, Volume 10,
1986, 29-49.
[25]. Here I am
paraphrasing Austin. See his essay, ‘AGATON and EY?AIMONIA in the ethics of Aristotle’ in
Philosophical Papers, (London: Oxford
University Press, 1970).
[26]. Derrida has shown
that he takes Searle seriously. His seriousness and patience is evident in the
engagement with Searle’s reply. Not only does Derrida devote an entire book to
explicating Searle’s misreading of him, he utilizes the entire English alphabet
from A to Z; letters that ordinary language philosophers have claim to have
mastered.
[27]. Diff, 7.
(Aventureux parce que cette stratégie n’est pas une simple stratégie au sens ou
l’on dit que la stratégie oriente la tactique depuis une visée finale, un telos ou le thème d’une domination,
d’une maîtrise et d’une réappropriation ultime du mouvement ou du cham), 7.
[28]. Searle’s
‘Statement of Teaching Philosophy’ located at the University of Berkeley web
site is illuminating for the hegemony it may inspire. We read, ‘Most of my
actual teaching efforts are devoted to undergraduates, and I can say now that
my favorite students to teach in the whole world are Berkeley upper-division
undergraduates in advanced undergraduate courses, the Philosophy of Mind, the
Philosophy of Language and Social Philosophy. Such students have a combination
of intelligence, enthusiasm, intellectual openness, and a kind of respectful
skepticism that I believe is unmatched anywhere in the world. When I teach in
Germany, for example, the first thing I have to do is train my students to act
like Berkeley students... They are not used to asking questions in a way that
challenges the professor while being at the same time respectful and observant
of the rigorous logical standards of the discipline. I teach them to do this,
and by the end of the semester they are raising their hands and arguing with me
as vigorously as my Berkeley students. But when you are not in Berkeley, it
takes an effort to get other students up to Berkeley level’. (my emphasis). One
would need to devote a book perhaps to fully analyze the supremacy and
close-mindedness that Searle is advocating. It is one thing to assert that
syntax or the symbolic is insufficient to establish semantics as Searle does in
his Chinese Room argument; another to argue that consciousness is as much an ordinary
biological phenomenon as is digestion. However when Searle asserts that
non-Berkeley philosophy students in Europe or elsewhere must be taught to think
like his Berkeley students he merely perpetuates an intolerance that Europe is
very familiar with.
[29]. In Limited Inc, 79.
[30]. The question of harm cannot be addressed fully within
this space. We would have to examine Searle’s intentions. Were his mis-readings
of Derrida done intentionally, deliberately, or on purpose? In Austin’s words,
Can something be done deliberately or purposely, but not intentionally? (Three
Ways of Spilling Ink, 278). If Searle’s mis-reading of Derrida was done
deliberately, but not intentionally, i.e. done as a quick decision, without
having the intention of doing harm, then we must conclude that his decision was
incorrect. Did Searle deliberately harm Derrida without intentionally doing so?
Was his ‘response’ done ‘on purpose’, yet not intentionally? Accidentally on
purpose, perhaps?
[31]. The distinction
between gossip and true speech was made by Jesus when he asked his disciples
the question, ‘Who do people say I am?’, and ‘Who do you say I am?’
[32]. In the concluding
statement of his Language Truth and Logic
( New York: Dover , 1952), 155, hereafter cited as LTL, A. J. Ayer makes the
vexing statement, ‘What we must recognize is that it is necessary for a
philosopher to become a scientist, in this sense, if he is to make any
substantial contributions towards the growth of human knowledge’. Is this then
the final outcome; the concluding statement of ordinary language philosophy –
‘philosophers become scientists’? Perhaps lexicographers who pose as
philosophers should consider becoming scientists. On page 103, Ayer contends
that ‘a strictly philosophical treatise on ethics should therefore make no
ethical pronouncements.’ However he fails to see that his statement is already
an ethical pronouncement.
[33]. A claim made by
Catharine Zuckert in ‘The Politics of Derridean Deconstruction’, Polity, Volume XXIII, Number 3, Spring
1991.
[34]. Edward Feser and
Steven Postrel, A Reality Principles: An Interview with John R. Searle, Reason Magazine February 2000.
[35]. Derrida has
responded to his debate with Foucault in a recent text entitled Resistances of Psychoanalysis.
[36]. John R. Searle,
‘Rationality and Realism: What is at Stake?’ Daedalus 122 (4) Fall 1993, 55-83.
[37]. I will allow the
American pragmatic philosopher John Dewey to answer Searle, proving perhaps
that answers can sometimes come from the grave. In his Theory of the Moral Life, (New York, Holt, 1960),84., Dewey writes,
‘Wrong consists in faithlessness to that upon which the wrongdoer commits when
he is judging and seeking for what is good to him... He contradicts, not as
Kant would have it, some abstract laws of reason, but the principle of
reciprocity when he refuses to extend to others the goods which he seeks for
himself’. Dewey clearly sees Searle’s problem when reading other philosophers.
[38]. Bertrand Russell,
The Problems of Philosophy (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1959), 156.
[39]. From the Greek kalein and the Lithuanian kalba or language.
[40]. Florian Rotzer, Conversations with French Philosophers,
translated from the German by Gary E. Aylesworth, (New Jersey: Humanities
Press, 1995), 52.
[41]. LTL, 59.
[42]. LTL, 96.
[43]. LTL, 108.
[44]. LTL, 112.
[45]. LTL, 44. Is the
ordinary language analyst a ‘misplaced grammarian’?
[46]. Leslie Armour,
‘The Origin of Values’, in Ethics and
Justifications, edited by Douglas Odegard (Edmonton: Academic Printing and
Publishing, 1988), 178.
[47]. Jacques Derrida,
‘Of the Humanities and the Philosophical Discipline: The Right to Philosophy
from the Cosmopolitical View’, Surfaces,
Volume 14, 7. French original not available.
[48]. Ibid, 7.
[49]. For
indeterminancy in Quine see his Word and
Object, (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1960), 26-80. And his Ontological Relativity and Other Essays, (New York: Columbia
University Press, 1969), 52. The link between Derrida and Quine needs to be
further explored. See Edith Wyschogrod’s groundbreaking essay, ‘Time and
Non-Being in Derrida and Quine’, Journal
of the British Society for Phenomenology, Volume 14, No.2, May 1983,
112-126.
Copyright © 2007 Minerva
All rights are reserved, but
fair and good faith use with full attribution may be made of this work for
educational or scholarly purposes.
Marko Zlomislic teaches philosophy at Conestoga
College, Institute of Technology and Advanced Learning in Kitchener, Canada. He
has recently published Jacques Derrida's Aporetic Ethics with Lexington Books.
Return to
Minerva (Volume 11) Main Page
Go to Top of This Page