ISSN 1393-614X Minerva
- An Internet Journal of Philosophy Vol. 11 2007
________________________________________________
Aisthesis and the Myth of Representation Carolyn
Lee Kane |
Abstract
Stemming from the term aisthesis (sense-perception),
Aesthetics is born. As Heidegger notes at the beginning of Being and Time (1929) aisthesis, for the pre-Socratic
Greeks was related to the process of revealing and concealing (alethia). Physical sensory perception
was trusted as knowledge. However, the history of Aesthetics has covered over
this sense of the term. From Antiquity on, a history of philosophy and
Aesthetic Theory alike begin a grand metaphysical project to separate sense
perception from reason and logos.
This project culminates in the Age of Reason, with the final subordination of
all aesthetics to the categories of representation.
Post-Kantian philosophy and Aesthetic Theory has attempted to invert this hierarchy, forcing representation into a subset of aesthetics. These efforts take the form of re-partition, re-integration, and re-turn. In this article I will trace these two trajectories and then conclude by arguing that Deleuze’s aesthetic theory ultimately undermines both of these projects, rejecting the “re” as the re- investment in abstract thought. By overturning metaphysical binaries, Deleuze presents us with a practice of art and philosophy that is grounded in radical difference, not the re-production of the same.
Representation
has only a single center, a unique and receding perspective, and in consequence
a false depth. It mediates everything, but mobilizes and moves nothing
(Deleuze, Difference and Repetition).
Stemming
from the term aisthesis
(sense-perception), Aesthetics is born. As Heidegger notes at the beginning of Being and Time (1929) aisthesis, for the pre-Socratic
Greeks was related to the process of revealing and concealing (alethia) (Heidegger 1962). Physical
sensory perception was trusted as knowledge. However, the history of Aesthetics
has covered over this sense of the term. From Antiquity on, a history of
philosophy and Aesthetic Theory alike begin a grand metaphysical project to
separate sense perception from reason and logos
(logic, reason). This project culminates in the Age of Reason, with the final
subordination of all aesthetics to the categories of representation.
Post-Kantian
philosophy and Aesthetic Theory has attempted to invert this hierarchy, forcing
representation into a subset of aesthetics. These efforts take the form of
re-partition, re-integration, and re-turn. In this article I will trace these
two trajectories and then I will conclude by arguing that Deleuze’s aesthetic
theory ultimately undermines both of these projects, rejecting the “re” as the
re- investment in abstract thought. By overturning metaphysical binaries,
Deleuze presents us with a practice of art and philosophy that is grounded in
radical difference, not the re-production of the same.
Part I Aesthetics &
Representation:
The Republic sorts
out three hierarchical levels for representation: the Ideal Form of chair, the
chair that a carpenter makes based on use (techne).
And the painter who paints only what appears as a chair (poesis). This third lower level is not even a chair actually, it is
only simulacra (Plato 1968). Painters are the third generation from truth (alethia), and they should be banished
because they present a danger to truth. “[T]he poetic man ... uses names and phrases to color each of
the arts. He himself doesn't understand; but he imitates in such a way as to
seem, to men whose condition is like his own and observe only speeches, to
speak very well.” (Plato 1968, 601a-b). The job of the poet
is to deceive, thus their very nature is contamination and danger, threatening
to weaken the strength of rationality (Plato 1968, 607c). This is especially
dangerous for “those who do not know” (children, the uneducated). Ideas on the
other hand (while immaterial Form) always “are” they do not come into being,
and thus they cannot be deceptive, they are immortal truth.
For
Kant aesthetic judgment is subjugated to categories of representation organized
by Reason. That is, aesthetics (formerly aisthesis)
is subservient to the a priori laws, laws that cannot be shown to be otherwise.
This is his endeavor to update the aesthetic theory inaugurated by Alexander
Baumgarten (1750) which attempted to turn aesthetics into a science by treating
the Beautiful with rational principles. But, Kant explains, to raise “its rules
to the rank of a science” is impossible, because aesthetics is empirical and
therefore, cannot be determined by a priori laws. This is deceiving. While Kant
acknowledges the empirical nature of aesthetics, he does so only under the
rubric of Reason. Thus “judgment” is called forth to complete the
endeavor.
Judgment
validates and corrects aesthetic practice. In the “Analytic of the Sublime,” a
rational account brings a nonrational occurrence into resolve. Kant determines
the sublime establishes an indeterminate relation between imagination and
Reason. This move marks what is known as the “Copernican turn” in aesthetic
philosophy where, instead of a somewhat symbiotic or co-extensive relation with
the material world, objects in the world conform to our knowledge of them (via
their representation in the categories).
So while Kant reserves a
place, and an importance, for the sublime as that which is “not” reason, it is
nonetheless, in the end, only in the service of reason. Its ultimate
unreasonability is justified because, Kant claims, it is there to “enforce
moral character.” In other words, with Kant paideai
becomes a transcendental religiosity. (Religion is, to note briefly, as Lewis
Mumford points out, a primary predecessor to rationalized and industrial
thought).[3] Reason and cognition will always come to
the rescue where the Imagination stops.[4]
The color of such an analytic project also posits itself as a “carte blanche” for the abstract mind: pure, objective and disembodied. In this way aesthetic interpretation and judgment is visual to the extent of “picturing” an idea in the mind. Representation is the visual. However, from Kant on, no single color or vision can be ascribed to “knowledge” as such, for the very concept becomes problematized in a post-Kantian spectrum.
Part II: Post-Kantian
Re-versals
The
cost aesthetic philosophy pays for severing its connection to the concrete and
material world is immeasurable. We could say the cost has been that of color
itself. Post-Kantian and Post-Enlightenment thought thus attempts to reverse
this hierarchy set forth in western metaphysics from Plato through Kant. This
reversal is the project of making representation subordinate to the primacy of
aesthetics. The myth of white reveals the truth of the deception of color.
Falsity lies not within deception, but rather within the claims to the
immediacy of objective representation and truth.
The nineteenth century begins, Jonathan
Crary notes, with the stable observer who represents the world with “pure
visibility,” that is, without a body.
However, Goethe in 1810 challenges this hegemony with his color
experiments. Conducted in explicit contrast to Newton who observed color in
isolated, “objective” conditions, Goethe focuses on the edges, the fringes of
color as an embodied, physiological, and subjective experience. Crary notes
that Goethe’s observations finally disrupt the Cartesian scopic regime that
dominated visuality in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries with abstract
representation.
Nietzsche
claims all representation is falsity. This is the truth of what aesthetics has
become. The sublime has become the “taming of horror through art,” the
rationalization that occurs before
art, i.e., Kant’s a priori. Reason produces aesthetics. Contemporary aesthetics
is disillusioned, thinking they see “truth” under the banner of Reason and
representation, they have only forgotten (lethe)
that language is metaphor (poesis)
and myth. Language and logos are naturalized
as “truth” and thus constitute the a priori of aesthetic “creation” as
Re-presentation.” The modern intellect holds “the arrogance inherent in
cognition” that “casts a blinding fog over the eyes and sense…it deceives them
about the value of their existence” and thus we now deceive in order to exist,
but the true crime is that we forget that we are deceiving. We have become
blind to our own self-deceptions (Nietzsche 1999, 142).
Heidegger
continues Nietzsche’s project. Also returning to the Greeks, he establishes
that aesthesis, the process of
unconcealing (alethia), suggests we
must understand the phrase “zoon logon
exon,” usually translated as “man is the rational animal,” as man
"with" logos. Heidegger’s
re-reading of Aristotle returns us to a time before “being” becomes an entity
because this metaphysical split is ultimately what produces the “thingliness”
of being; the “Metaphysics of Substance” which reifies both man and Reason.
Thus
logos belongs in life. It is a part
of life, not an instrument, a thing or entity, but is folded into the soul, in psuche (soul). Not only then can we not
explain life through logos (reason, and thus; representation) as logos is in life, but also, we construct our
life-worlds, our being-in-the-world, aesthetically (aisthesis). While Being and
Time does not lend itself to aesthetic theory, it is nonetheless a project
in Phenomenology which by definition
privileges life lived through sensory experience (aisthesis). Dasein must “nurture and cultivate” (paideia) life and reason with “care” (sorge).
Logos does not automatically generate
a priori laws, but rather, order springs from the ground of aisthetic
life choices (Heidegger 1962, 225).[5]
“The truth of aisthesis and of seeing of ‘ideas’ is the primordial kind of uncovering”
(Heidegger 1962, 269). As Nietzsche has said before him, the “only
justification for existence is aesthetic.”
However,
for Heidegger, the practical possibilities for the fulfillment of paideia, after the advent of modern
technology, are glib. His concept of Gestell
suggests an enframing and imprisonment that thwarts the impossibility of
returning to the ground of aisthesis. At any rate, Being and Time lays the groundwork for Derrida who continues this
project, showing the infinite play in the myth of representation. For Derrida
representation is always already haunted by “excess.” For instance, the
inscription of writing is only ever a pharmakon:
both cure and poison, both inscribing and erasing meaning in the same gesture.
With Derrida, the possibility of gleaning any stable meaning or cognitive
certainty is foreclosed. In part this is because simulacra for Derrida are only
copies of copies. Thus, they are still reliant on a copy: model
representational schema which does not allow for difference.[6]
Yet
certainly life, on a practical level, is not constituted by pure affect, play,
and sensation exclusively, but is equally accompanied by cognition, optical knowledge,
and abstraction. Deleuze, following Nietzsche’s excavation, offers an account
of aesthetics that includes the qualities of sensation, affect, play, and the
production of meanings, cognition, and abstraction. Before giving a concrete
example of this, Deleuze “clears the ground” of philosophical clichés.
Representation
is only ever the re-production of the Same; static thought which cannot
“capture the affirmed world of difference. Representation has only a single center,
a unique and receding perspective, and in consequence a false depth. It
mediates everything, but mobilizes and moves nothing.…” (Deleuze 1994,
55-56). Thus aesthetic practice, as an
essentially creative practice, must utilize difference, without subordination
to representation. Yet the reality of our contemporary world is one of falsity
and dead commodity forms. Thus the play of pure difference does not pander to
these forms as a primary or organic
model, but emerges from them, for-itself, in-itself. Difference “demands its
own Idea, its own singularity at the level of Ideas” (Deleuze 1994, 27). Unlike
Derrida then, difference accrues meaning. Thus the task of allowing Difference
for itself is also the task of liberating the Idea to its own thought. The
singular Idea which is always already simulacra. This is the project of
overturning metaphysics and the oppressive myth of the truth of representation.
Because representation for Deleuze is only
ever a copy that replicates the model, thwarting the possibility that art or
philosophy could be creative, it is
simulacra that do not re-plicate, and thus always generate the new. This
problem is rooted, and solved, In Plato’s Sophist. “Plato proposes to isolate the false claimant
par excellence, the one who lays claim to everything without right” (Deleuze 1994, 61). But the task of separating the authentic
(model) form the counterfeit (copy) becomes the very problem of the text
itself. By the end of The Sophist,
the “Stranger can no longer be distinguished from Socrates.” The sophist, the
“one who raises everything to the level of simulacra and maintains them in that
state” reveals the truth of difference -- the confusion of authenticating, not
of identifying (representation) (Deleuze 1994, 68). Thus Plato is actually the first to “overturn
Platonism,” yet he also quickly retreats to the safety of judgment.
Deleuze’s
aesthetic theory is not subordinate to representation, nor is representation
subordinate to aesthetics. Because aesthetics is creative production from
radical difference, aesthetics by definition excludes the hierarchy implied in
theories of representation. In this view, Theories
of Representation have no status for the visual domain. Aesthetic practice
is built from simulacra that expose the (Dionysian) ground of radical
difference. This process is exemplified in Deleuze’s concept of the Diagram.
In
order to build a diagram, like the Body without Organs, an artist must first
clear the ground of “clichés.” Everyone already possesses “psychic
clichés”––conventions, rigidified thought, laws of representation which prevent
becoming. This is why Deleuze claims that “every painter is already in the
canvas” before he arrives. To this extent representation exists in art, but
only insofar as it is the role of art to break with these “givens” (Deleuze 2002). We could say representation
as such; dead forms and commodity objects, are the found format for this
aesthetic practice.
As
Daniel Smith notes, the concept of the diagram is borrowed from Charles
Peirce’s semiotics, where the diagram is “an icon of intelligible relations.”
While Deleuze follows this lead, for him a diagram is not a copy or an index to
a prior reference, but rather “he assigns to the diagram a much stronger
genetic role: the diagrammatic or abstract machine does not function to
represent, even something real, but rather constructs a real that is yet to
come, a new type of reality” (Smith in Deleuze 2002) The diagram must go
through a catastrophe to break with clichés. Through “wiping, scrubbing, and
brushing” the canvas, the diagram dismantles the optical world. The work
reaches a blockage and stopping, but at the same time, it will re-inject itself
into a new world.
While Deleuze’s aesthetic theory is perhaps
the antithesis of Kant’s, he is still indebted to him. This stopping, the
catastrophe, is Deleuze’s version of the limit of thought reached in Kant’s
aesthetic sublime. However, Deleuze will invert the categories that ground the
relationship between object and subject that ensure the safe status of
knowledge, identity, and the repetition of the same. With Kant, the aesthetic
sublime is the inability of Reason to rescue the Imagination; leaving the
subject in a state of chaotic awe. The result is a chaos, a “dizzying and what strikes
the senses is unrecognizable, it goes beyond any possibility of comprehension.”
But unlike Kant, for Deleuze, Reason does not ever come to the rescue. The
“entire edifice and structure of perception is in the process of exploding. In
the grips of the sublime, “I can no longer apprehend
the successive parts, I cannot reproduce
the preceding parts as the following one arrives, and finally, I can no longer recognize what the thing is. I can no
longer qualify the object in general”” (Smith in Deleuze and Deleuze 2002,
xix). Thus the edifice for a priori of
knowledge collapses, overturning the subjugation of aesthetic composition to
epistemology, and instead placing knowledge in the service of the priority of
aesthetic experience. We have cleared the ground of clichés and can see the
Dionysian ground of new life and new thought. The diagram can only ever produce
radical difference.
The
limits of reason and cognition force us into an other kind of perceptual
functioning; the eye is pushed towards a haptic perception. Haptic imagery does
not have to report to higher faculty, schema, or model of representation (Deleuze 2002, 111-112).[7]
In other words, it is beyond metaphysical order, the hierarchy of thought, or
the privileging of intelligibility and reason. Haptic visuality is a perception
that is grounded in aisthesis,
opening the work to the “logic of sensation”: abstraction of affects and
sensory perception that gives new laws and meaning to create concrete new
thought––thought “without an Image.”
In
order to do this successfully, a diagram demands balance between abstraction
(laws) and chaos (Dionysian ground). It “must not eat away at a painting too
violently, it must remain limited in space and time; it must remain operative
and controlled.” The artist must “prevent the diagram from proliferating”
(Deleuze 2002, 89). Like the "Body
without Organs," it cannot be built “with a sledgehammer” but one must use
a “very fine file.” In this way a diagram is the distinct from Derrida’s, and
Plato’s, uncontrollable and infinitely aberrant pharmakon. A diagram is “indeed chaos, catastrophe, but it is also
a germ of order or rhythm” (Deleuze
2002, 83), that which “produces a life for tomorrow” (Deleuze 1999, 1976). This
new life and meaning is not organic––it springs from simulacra; a “synthesis”
of inorganic life. This is also unlike Heidegger’s Dasein then, which is a
hermeneutic representation, rooted in the anthropocentric “humanities.” Radical difference is already privy to the
truth of the ground of falsity; the “Powers of the False.” Diagrams create from
synthetic and mechanically re-produced color, not the abstract myth of white
light.
Here is an example of a diagram that uses
color, a long excerpt taken from Deleuze’s essay on the artist Gérard Fromanger
and his piece, Bayeux Violet:
…[A] little fellow in
the background is made green and cold, to give even more heat by contrast to
the potentially hot violet. Yet this isn’t enough to bring the painting to life.
A yellow and hot man in the foreground will induce or re-induce the violet,
bring it into action through the intermediary of the green and over the green.
But the cold green is now alone, out of the circuit, as if it had exhausted its
function in one go. This now has to be supported, reintroduced into the
painting, reanimated or reactivated into the painting as a whole, by a third
cold blue figure behind the yellow…. It also sometimes happens that there
emerges in the photograph a point of resistance to its being transformed into a
living painting. It leaves behind a residue as in Bayeux Violet, where a last figure in the foreground group remains
indeterminate.… The residue finds itself reinjected into the painting, so much
so that the painting works on the basis of the photographic residue just as
much as the photograph comes to function on the basis of the constituent
colours of the painting (Deleuze 1999, 66-68).
The
play and circulation of elements opens the image as simulacra. Simulacra is
like the “memoire involontaire” of Bergson (not the unconscious of
representation), where virtual and actual oscillate and repeat. The two are
essentially different, but their appearance is one of resemblance. Simulacra is
thus the repetition of difference, repetition with a difference. Here the “re”
of re-petition is inorganic and nonhierarchical, it not re-presentation but
instead it is the indiscernability of a haptic perception that forces new
thoughts and relations to emerge. Bringing out the colds and hots of the past,
selected from the dead commodity world, Fromanger’s diagram circulates colors
and vitalizes dead commodities.
To
restate, diagrams are not concerned with representation, because representation
is precisely the myth and cliché they destroy. However, what we do see in a
diagram is a negotiation between affect and meaning, a modulation that combines
new meanings and sense from the ground of pure difference. A diagram must
“choose for oneself” (paideia),
ultimately supporting an aesthetic practice that is beyond “beyond good and
evil,” “beyond Judgment” and beyond the oppression of the myth of
Representation (Deleuze 2001, 28).
Representation has been
shown as the attempt to control aesthetic practice through reason (logos). Even up until Kant’s use of the
term “Judgment,” aesthetics is treated under a priori categories of
representation. Up to this point, knowledge is desired as white. The post-Kantian aesthetic philosophers expose
this myth and invert the relationship between representation and aesthetics.
They begin the process of clearing the ground of clichés by dirtying the myth
of pristine truth. Left without this security, we find only simulacra and aisthetic knowledge, giving us
nothing but color.
This story of aesthetics in
the history of philosophy runs parallel to broader issues of art production, as
with, for instance, the deployment of color in the history of western art.
Certainly contemporary art embraces, if not celebrates, a color aesthetic that
is synthetic and derogatory. For instance, the markedly artificial hues of pop
art, Warhol, and even Duchamp’s poignant observation in 1910 that any painting
made after the advent of mechanical reproduction is always already a
“readymade.” This claim, Duchamp can make, because any color pigment produced
after the industrial revolution, in order to be employed for common use, as
well to be used en plein air, must
necessarily be mass-produced by machines. The mass production of color
pigments, and thus the standardization of the color palette in artistic
production, marks the mechanization of color technology. After mechanical
reproduction, neither art nor cultural production can lay claim to the myth of
the purity of the canvas, nor the “innocence” of the color palette that accompanies
it. So it may seem then that the celebration of synthetic aesthetics and an
impure palette in the contemporary art world, in the works of Warhol, Pop Art,
or Contemporary painting, may return us to a new life in the synthetic and
post-industrial world. Or, on the contrary, perhaps the now standardized
contemporary and postmodern aesthetic of impurity and difference is, once
again, like post-structuralism and representation, an infinite return of the
same.
REFERENCES
Derrida,
Jacques 1987, Dissemination. trans.
Barbara Johnson. Chicago : University Press,
Fromanger,
Gérard 1974, Bayeux Violet.
http://www.mchampetier.com/sitephp/phpfr/estampe/8629_Fromanger+G%E9rard_1fromangerjanv074.html
(Retrieved August 24, 2007).
Heidegger,
Martin 1962, Being and Time. trans.
John Macquarrie & Edward Robinson. New York: Harper.
Heidegger,
Martin 1982, “The Question Concerning Technology.” The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays. New York:
Harper.
Kant, Immanuel
1951 Critique of Pure Reason. trans.
Norman Kemp Smith. London: Palgrave, 2003.
Kant,
Immanuel Critique of Judgment. trans
J.H. Bernard. New York, Hafner.
Mumford, Lewis
1934, Technics and Civilization. New
York: Harcourt, Brace and Company.
Nietzsche,
Friedrich 1993, The Birth of Tragedy out
of the Spirit of Music. trans. Shaun Whiteside. New York: Penguin.
Nietzsche,
Friedrich 1999, “Art and Lies in an Extra-Moral Sense” Birth of Tragedy and Other Writings. trans. Ronald Speirs. New
York: Cambridge UP.
Plato 1968, The Republic of Plato. trans. Allan Bloom. Basic Books.
NOTES
[1] A theme
Heidegger will pick up on in his “Care as the Being of Dasein” in Book VI of Being and Time.
[2] The
Greek word paideia is defined as
schooling, character development, and training. Deleuze will pick up on this
concept of paideia in his discussion
of the training and “apprenticeship” needed to “clear the ground of clichés.”
In this way too, one decides for oneself, as creative act, not the
re-production of externally imposed laws.
[3] Mumford,
Lewis. Technics and Civilization. Here
Mumford gives the example of church bells organizing the time of the day, monks
living in cells and ordering their life around highly calculated and rational
schedules.
[4] Deleuze
will pick up on this theme of the limit of thought in the aesthetic sublime,
but he will not allow Reason to recuperate it.
[5] At the same time, for Heidegger, “Care” (Sorge) in German, is interpreted as also
including “anxiety,” and thus explains the tendency for Dasein to “turn away”
in the face of itself and “flee” from being-in-the-world, but this is rather
the problem of modern world, not, Dasein as such.
[6] See Paul Patton, “Anti-Platonism and Art,” for more on the distinction
between Derrida and Deleuze on the simulacra.
[7]
The
distinction is that haptic visuality forces the eye to function “like a hand,”
that is, as a kind of touch. Whereas optical vision relies only on the eye as a
cognitive, intellectual organ. These theories are advanced by Alois Riegl and
Wilhelm Worringer.
Copyright
© 2007 Minerva
All
rights are reserved, but fair and good faith use with full attribution may be
made of this work for educational or scholarly purposes.
Carolyn Kane is a PhD
Candidate in the Department of Media, Culture, and Communication at New York University.
She is currently researching her dissertation on “The Aesthetics of Electronic
Color”.
Return to
Minerva (Volume 11) Main Page Go to Top of
This Page