ISSN 1393-614X Minerva
- An Internet Journal of Philosophy Vol. 11 2007
__________________________________________________
Nietzsche, Spinoza, and the
Ethological Conception of Ethics Paolo
Bolańos |
Abstract
This paper attempts a
parallelism, through the French philosopher Gilles Deleuze’s conception of a practical philosophy, between the
thoughts of Friedrich Nietzsche (one of the most celebrated, if not, the most
celebrated, appropriated, and abused philosophers of the past century) and
Benedict de Spinoza (an almost unsung 18th Century Dutch
thinker). Inspired by Nietzsche’s image
as a nomadic thinker, Deleuze presents us with a more convincing image of
Spinoza: a man who is closer to LIFE.
The specific aspect of the Nietzsche-Spinoza relation I want to discuss
in what follows is the difference between “morality” and “ethics” — it will
become clear that with Nietzsche and Spinoza, ethics has an “ethological”
basis. It is hoped that the distinction between morality and ethics will
illuminate what Deleuze sees in both Nietzsche and Spinoza as a basic notion of
philosophical thinking — a way of thinking which is beyond good and evil, that is, beyond moralistic ontology.
“There is more wisdom in your body than in
your deepest philosophy.” – F. Nietzsche, Human,
All Too Human.
“Out of life’s school of
war. What does not destroy me, makes me
stronger.” – F. Nietzsche, Twilight
of the Idols.
“I have
striven not to laugh at human actions, not to weep at them, nor to hate them,
but to understand them.” – B. Spinoza, Tractatus
Theologico-Politicus.
Ethics
amidst Nihilism
The most pressing question
amidst Friedrich Nietzsche’s prognosis of the cultural disease he calls
“nihilism” is the question about the status of “morality” in our contemporary
age (and for those who purport themselves to be trendy, the term
‘postmodernity’ seems to convey precisely the crisis of morality). It is not at all imprecise to note that the
crisis of morality is a direct consequence of the crisis of rationality. Nietzsche illustrates the latter in his
declaration of the “death of God” – a statement which has caused much
controversy among both the initiated and uninitiated in Nietzsche’s corpus. A
levelheaded attempt at understanding Nietzsche’s philosophy presupposes a grasp
of the context of the death of God. One
totally misses the point if one simply interprets the statement as a
disgruntled atheistic rant! Interpreting
the death of God from a purely religious context undermines its epistemological and ontological implications – that the statement itself is a defiance
of the dominance of Reason. This means that what has died is a principle of
transcendence that unconditionally grounds the claims of classical epistemology
and ontology. I am not, of course, denying the fact that the death of God is also a religious statement; but it is
only religious inasmuch as religion (especially the Christian one) only makes
sense by tacitly deploying the postulates of epistemology and metaphysics. In
other words, the presuppositions of Christian religion are warranted through
the signature of Reason.
Thus, ‘God’ is just another
term for Reason or for a reified principle of transcendence considered as
universal and unconditionally binding. Nietzsche violently beats the bell with
a hammer in order to wake us up from our illusion of transcendence. This is the meaning, however metaphoric, of
the death of God. It is in this basic metaphysical bias, the presence of essences, that traditional moral
philosophical discourse is based. If
classical moral philosophy is based on purported transcendent categories that
are binding, then the uproar of Nietzsche’s madman is a critique of such essentialist
thinking. Nietzsche’s philosophy is both a critique and an introduction of a
counterculture, that of “nomadism” – a philosophy that does not seek to be
bound to abrogated universal essences that are hostile to LIFE (thus,
nihilistic), but rather seeks to create, enhance, and celebrate LIFE. The creation, enhancement, and celebration of
life, however, presuppose a shift of mindset. Nietzsche’s detachment from
essentialism perturbs the practice of grounding morality in universal
principles.
Hence, the question of the
very possibility of still grounding
ethics in ontology and practice becomes pressing. I believe that the shift of
mindset begins in a terminological shift: we have to make sense of the meaning
of the concept “ethics” and how it relates to, and is differentiated from, the
concept “morality.” My paper will deal with precisely the nuance between
morality and ethics.
A significant aspect of this
present paper is an attempt at a parallelism, through Gilles Deleuze’s
(1925-1995) conception of a practical philosophy, between the thoughts of
Nietzsche (one of the most celebrated, if not, the most celebrated,
appropriated, and abused philosophers of the past century) and Benedict de
Spinoza (1632-1677, an almost unsung 18th Century Dutch thinker).
Inspired by Nietzsche’s image as a nomadic thinker, Deleuze presents us with a
more convincing image of Spinoza: a man who is closer to LIFE. The specific aspect of the Nietzsche-Spinoza
relation I want to discuss is the difference between “morality” and “ethics” –
it will become clear later that with Nietzsche and Spinoza, ethics has an
“ethological” basis. It is hoped that
the distinction between morality and ethics will illuminate what Deleuze sees
in both Nietzsche and Spinoza as a basic notion of philosophical thinking – a
way of thinking which is beyond good and
evil, that is, beyond moralistic ontology.
From
Transcendence to Immanence
Perhaps the best point of
departure from which a notion of “ethical thinking” can follow through is a discussion
of a critique of traditional ontology which Deleuze thinks is found in both
Nietzsche and Spinoza. This results in a
typology between two ontologies: that is, between the ontology of transcendence (commonly referred to as
metaphysics) and the ontology of immanence.
Later on, it will become clear that for both Spinoza and Nietzsche, the
ontology of transcendence is tied to what may be referred to as “moral
thinking.” Hence, the critique of metaphysics evinced by both philosophers is,
in essence, a critique of moral thinking. Ultimately, for Spinoza, a view of
the world can manifest itself as either moral or ethical. In relation to this, Deleuze comments: “The
theory of power according to which actions and passions of the body accompany
actions and passions of the soul amounts to an ethical vision of the world”
(Deleuze 1990, p. 257). At first glance, the relation between ontology and ethics is not that conspicuous; nevertheless, this is precisely the
fulcrum of Spinoza’s major work – a work on ontology which he interestingly
named Ethics, and this title already
arouses our curiosity. After all the hefty geometrical discussions on
metaphysics, anthropology, and psychology, Spinoza claims that the theme that
underlies his work is ethical in
nature. This, Spinoza thinks, can only be accounted for after a comprehensive
understanding of how singularities follow necessarily from one single
substance. Ultimately, Spinoza’s synthetic method demonstrates how we can,
through wisdom, attain happiness or the good life, that is, the ethical life.
Moreover, the proper understanding of this ethical life is tethered to a type
of ontology that can interpret the various aspects of normativity. Deleuze
deems ontology to be “ethological”; that is, it is primarily concerned with the
material conditions of human life in both its natural and social contexts. In
other words, ontology is concerned with modes
of being or singularities. More
specifically, he refers to ethology as “the study of the relations of speed and
slowness, of the capacities of being affected that characterize each thing”
(Deleuze 1988, p. 125). Metaphysics, on
the other hand (the handmaiden of morality), is concerned with essence or something beyond what simply is. Metaphysics is concerned with transcendence, something other than, and purportedly higher than,
being. For Deleuze, presupposing a beyond is not the proper task of
ontology. He takes ontology in its most rudimentary sense, a discourse of what
simply is. Following Deleuze, I am
arguing that this ethological conception of ontology is the basis of Spinoza’s
ethical worldview. This is what Deleuze sees as the genius of Spinoza’s Ethics: the substitution of ethics for
morality; what the Ethics presents,
therefore, is an anti-juridical ontology.
Spinoza’s critique of
metaphysics begins with an inquisition into the ontological status of the
“body” or of “bodies.” He writes in the
third book of the Ethics:
For indeed, no one has
yet determined what the body can do, that is, experience has not yet taught
anyone what the body can do from the laws of Nature alone, insofar as Nature is
only considered to be corporeal, and what the body can do only if it is
determined by the mind. For no one has
yet come to know the structure of the body so accurately that he could explain
all its functions – not to mention that many things are observed in the lower
animals which far surpass human ingenuity, and that sleepwalkers do a great
many things in their sleep which they
would not dare to awake. This shows well
enough that the body itself, simply from the laws of its own nature, can do
many things which its mind wonders at (Spinoza 1994, pp. 155-156).
Deleuze interprets the above
passage as Spinoza’s war cry (Deleuze 1990, p. 255). This initiates the Ethics into a criticism of the traditional conception of the body,
that is, the body as being inferior and obedient to the commands of the mind.
We find a very similar passage in Nietzsche’s Nachlaß:
The human body, in which
the most distant and most recent past of all organic development again becomes
living and corporeal, through which and over and beyond which a tremendous
inaudible stream seems to flow: the body is a more astonishing idea than the
old “soul”.[1]
In his Nietzsche and Philosophy, Deleuze takes note of Nietzsche’s point
of departure: “What is the body? … Being composed of a plurality of irreducible
forces the body is a multiple phenomenon, its unity is that of a multiple
phenomenon, a ‘unity of domination’” (Deleuze 1983, p. 40). The internal dynamism of the body is,
therefore, Nietzsche’s point of departure, as it is also the case for Spinoza.
Furthermore, Deleuze writes, “In a body the superior or dominant forces are
known as active and the inferior or
dominated forces are known as reactive”
(Ibid.). Later I will talk of the
ethical import of active and reactive forces as manifestations of
power and will relate them to Spinoza’s notion of the conatus.
From a Spinozistic point of
view, Deleuze attempts to show how Nietzsche puts to the fore a philosophy of
immanence by seeing the body as the originary stratum of forces.[2] By giving the body this status,
Nietzsche is able to move beyond the metaphysical or “essentialist”
interpretation of forces. According to Deleuze, Nietzsche conceives of “Subtle
relations of power and of evaluation between different ‘selves’ that conceal
but also express other kinds of forces – forces of life, forces of thought . .
.” (Deleuze 2001, p. 59). Forces emanate from bodies which are assemblages of
forces; the body is a unified multiplicity, an assemblage. By declaring the body as an assemblage of
forces, the value given to a “transcendent subject” becomes nil. This is
Nietzsche’s way of criticizing and overcoming the Modern adherence to an
autonomous “subject.”
Spinoza’s war cry — a war cry
against the ontology of transcendence — is made clear, in that he says, that “The object of the idea constituting the
human mind is the body, or a certain
mode of extension which actually exists, and nothing else” (Spinoza 1994,
p. 123). Moreover, “An idea that excludes
the existence of our body cannot be in our mind, but is contrary to it”
(Spinoza 1994, p. 160). On this note,
the emphasis on existence is quite
clear. The proper object of ontology is existence,
and for Deleuze, existence is interpreted as a life of pure immanence. What
ontology presupposes is a realm or what Deleuze calls a field: this field is what we call LIFE. Hence, in this context, Nietzsche and Spinoza
present a unique strand of ontology – one which takes the singularities of bodies as point of departure. And since they break
away from transcendent principles, they make it possible to interpret
singularities from the purview of “power” (puissance),
as opposed to “essence.” Bodies, moreover, are understood as “singularities”
(each body/force is unique from other bodies), as opposed to belonging to a
single “universal” category or genus.
It is this movement from essences to singularities, that is, from the metaphysics of the soul to the ontology
of the body, which also marks the movement from moralistic thinking to ethical
thinking, that is, from a discourse of the molar to a discourse of the molecular.
This is what Deleuze refers to as the movement from the “dogmatic image of
thought” to the “new image of thought” or a “thought without image,” that is,
not a binding image in the
traditional sense, but, rather, an image which
does not restrict thinking to obsolete postulates and by being aware that
thinking has the tendency to be bound to dogmatism (Cf. Deleuze 1994, pp.
129-167). Through this new image of
thought, Deleuze makes sense of a counterculture which is a perspective that
resists traditional or representational metaphysics and epistemology. Deleuze
takes the Nietzschean reversal of Platonism or the transmutation of values as
the point of departure. Interestingly enough, Deleuze also finds the same
transvaluation of values in Spinoza. According to Deleuze, we have to abandon
our old image of the world in order to free ourselves from the obscurantism of
foundationalist or essentialist thinking. It is only through the transmutation
of values that we can make sense of a life of pure immanence: an ethical life
of singularities, of forces.
Force
and Power or Bodies and Conatus
Deleuze argues that a body is
a force, and that it could be anything: “an animal, a body of sounds, a mind or
an idea; it can be a linguistic corpus, a social body, a collectivity” (Deleuze
1988, p. 127). Spinoza’s concept of the body, therefore, does not solely refer
to human bodies, but instead to forces or singularities. As such, strictly
speaking, there is no essential difference between the noble and the base aside
from that of degrees of power. Bodies are not differentiated on the basis of
formal genera, but rather on kinetic
and dynamic terms. This is what is
meant by “relations of speed and slowness” and “the capacities of being
affected.” Deleuze writes:
There is no difference
between wise man and fool, reasonable and demented men, strong man and weak.
They do of course differ in the kind of affections that determine their effort
to preserve in existence. But each tries equally to preserve himself, and has
as much right as he has power, given the affections that actually exercise his
capacity to be affected (Deleuze 1990, p. 258).
In this sense, therefore,
power is a matter of degree and that power springs forth from nature itself.
Power, according to Nietzsche, is a “primitive form of affect, that all other
affects are only developments of it” (WP
III, 688). We need to pay heed to the
value he accorded the conception of the will to power itself: “But what is life? Here we need a new, more definite formulation
of the concept ‘life.’ My formula for it
is: Life is will to power” (WP II,
254). We can also read in Beyond Good and Evil: “The world viewed
from inside, the world defined and determined according to its ‘intelligible
character’ – it would be ‘will to power’ and nothing else” (BGE II, 36). The value of the will to power is itself the
value accorded to life – the only undeniable ontological fact. Deleuze offers
us a more convincing interpretation of the will to power: “power” is explained
as the principle of affirmative and negative evaluations. Since it is the most primitive form of affect,
and thus unnoticed, other more conspicuous affects (forces) are merely
developments or manifestations of it. For Deleuze the will to power is both the
quantitative and qualitative element of bodies.
He is clear and emphatic: power “doesn’t mean (or at least doesn’t
primarily mean) that the will wants
power or wishes to dominate” (Deleuze
2001, p. 73). Power animates the will;
power thus is never separated from willing. Every willing entails a
manifestation of power. This means that there is no willing without power, for
in the first place it is power which determines whether the moment of willing
itself is either affirmative or negative. Deleuze provides a formula which
explains the relation of will to power and its symptoms (forces): “Force is
what can, will to power is what wills” (Deleuze 1983, p. 50). Forces are the
external manifestations of the will to power; all symptoms proceed from this
genealogical element. The interaction between forces presupposes the element of
encounter. This encounter between bodies is agonistic – it entails that a force
struggles to win over or conquer other forces. The struggle between forces
ensues from their very capacity to be affected in a relation of forces.
The above conception of power
is not the principle of ethical difference, inasmuch as all singularities
strive to preserve their own being or, in other words, strive to express their
power and the difference between two expressions is only one of degree. Deleuze
argues that the ethical difference between bodies (e.g., between two men) “relates to the kind of affections that
determine our conatus” (Deleuze 1990, p. 261). Spinoza writes in the Ethics, “Each thing, as far
as it can by its own power, strives to persevere in its being” (Spinoza
1994, p. 159). This means that power is the genealogical element of forces, of
expressions; and since, at the natural standpoint, all things are driven by the
principle of power – ethologically this is how bodies, in general, behave. But
since the perseverance of bodies implies that they have to encounter other
bodies, and a body acts differently depending on the type of body it
encounters, power is also affected by the power that comes from the outside.
Spinoza defines an affect as “affections of the body by which the body’s power
of acting is increased or diminished, aided or restrained, and at the same
time, the ideas of these affections” (Spinoza 1994, p. 154). Hence, the
encounter between bodies entails either an “active” or “reactive” response from
a body. An “adequate cause of any of
these affections,” according to Spinoza, is “an action” and an inadequate cause
is “a passion” (Ibid.). I reckon that
this is the point where the ethical difference
between the noble and the base, the strong and the weak, manifests.
This is also the point where
the resemblance between Nietzsche and Spinoza is most striking. All phenomena
or expressions are to be treated as if treating symptoms of health or sickness. Nietzsche discriminates between active and reactive
forces as symptoms of health and sickness — more precisely, between healthy and sick ways of appraising life — between healthy and unhealthy
lifestyles. This genealogical difference calls for the prognosis of who, in the first place, is interpreting
life: “One may ask: ‘who then interprets?’ for the interpretation itself is a
form of the will to power …” (WP III,
556). Meanwhile, Spinoza, for his part, thinks that the possession of adequate
ideas allows one to actively express his power; on the other hand, the weak
only possesses inadequate ideas and, as a result, does not fully express the
potentialities of his power, thus succumbs to passion. Joy, which results from the active manifestation of the conatus,
already speaks of a symptom of health, and sadness,
which is a product of the infiltration of outside forces (where these forces
act as poisons), is a symptom of sickness. For Spinoza, this is the typology
between good and bad: On the one hand, “The individual,” writes Deleuze, “will be
called good who strives ... to organize
his encounters, to join with whatever agrees with his nature,” (Deleuze 1988,
pp. 22-23) and, on the other hand, one is bad
when he “lives haphazardly, who is content to undergo the effects of his
encounters, but wails and accuses every time the effect undergone does not
agree with him and reveals his impotence” (Deleuze 1988, p. 23).
What
does it Mean to Think Ethically?
Thinking ethically entails,
for Deleuze, a radicalization of our conception of philosophy as a whole. To be
specific, it entails a movement from the ontology of transcendence to the
ontology of immanence. And because
ethics inheres in ontology, this radical philosophy also entails a movement
from moralistic thinking to ethical thinking, that is, ethological
thinking. Deleuze summarizes this
radical movement:
Ethics,
which is to say, a typology of immanent modes of existence, replaces Morality,
which always refers existence to transcendent values. Morality is the judgment
of God, the system of Judgment. But
Ethics overthrows the system of judgment. The opposition of values (Good-Evil)
is supplanted by the qualitative difference of modes of existence (good-bad)
(Deleuze 1988, p. 23).
Ethics, in the above sense,
could also refer to Deleuze’s distinction between the “good life” (ethics
[Stoicism]) and the “moral law” (morality [Kantianism]). Deleuze actually takes
the lead of Foucault on “subjectification,”
wherein subjectification is opposed to the moral conception of the subject.[3] In
place of morality, we have an ethical and aesthetic conception of the subject,
that is, a subject who partakes of knowledge and power as an assemblage of
forces (Cf. Deleuze 1995, p. 114). This image of the subject — as opposed to a
transcendent subjectivity — ensues from an immanent view of the world; and the
ethical subject becomes who/what he
is by encountering forces which are the very conditions of his existence. In
one of his commendable essays, Yirmiyahu Yovel writes about the affinities
between Spinoza and Nietzsche. According to Yovel, “If Spinoza has started the
modern philosophy of immanence and underlies it throughout, then Nietzsche
brings it to its most radical conclusion” (Yovel 1986, p. 183-203). Further, “Both
declare the ‘death’ of the transcendent God, and see life within immanence as
all there is” (Ibid.). Yovel argues
that Nietzsche’s conception of the eternal return (referring to The Gay Science 341) “is the utmost
affirmation of immanence,” that the “eternal recurrence dramatizes the
inescapability of immanence …” (Ibid.).
This paper is by no means an
exhaustive appraisal of the Nietzsche-Spinoza relation. What I have done is
merely to scratch the surface of this enterprise by amplifying some elective
affinities that Deleuze himself has already put forward in some of his
writings. Deleuze thinks with Nietzsche and Spinoza by underscoring the drama of their thoughts. At the margin of a Nietzschean and
Spinozist critique of metaphysics, a metaphysics which they deem inimical to
life, we are offered a fresh sensibility to life – a de-deified world, a world
translated back to nature, a vast plane of immanence which has within it a multiplicity of forces; it
has a within, but it has no beyond.
REFERENCES
DELEUZE, Gilles and
GUATTARI, Felix. 1987. A Thousand
Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia, trans. by Brian Massumi.
___________. 1994. What is Philosophy?, trans. by Hugh
Tomlinson and Graham Burchell.
DELEUZE, Gilles. 1983. Nietzsche and Philosophy, trans. by Hugh
Tomlinson.
___________. 1988. Spinoza: Practical Philosophy, trans. by
Robert Hurley.
___________. 1990. Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza,
trans. by Martin Joughin.
___________. 1994. Difference & Repetition, trans. by
Paul Patton.
___________. 1995. Negotiations 1972-1990, trans. by Martin
Joughin.
___________. 2001. Pure Immanence: Essays on a Life, trans.
by Anne Boyman.
NIETZSCHE, Friedrich. 1966. Beyond Good and Evil: Prelude to a
Philosophy of the Future, trans. by Walter Kaufmann.
___________. 1967. The Will to Power, trans. by Walter
Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale.
SMITH, Daniel W. 1988. “The Place of
Ethics in Deleuze’s Philosophy: Three Questions of Immanence.” In Deleuze
and Guattari: New Mappings in Politics, Philosophy, and Culture.
___________. 2007. “Deleuze and the Question of Desire:
Toward an Immanent Theory of Ethics.” In Parrhesia
Number 2, pp.66-78. Online: www.parrhesiajournal.org/parrhesia02/parrhesia02_smith.pdf.
SPINOZA, Benedict.
1994. Ethics, trans. by Edwin Curley. In A Spinoza Reader.
YOVEL, Yirmiyahu. 1986.
“Nietzsche and Spinoza: amor fati and
amor dei.” In Nietzsche as Affirmative Thinker.
NOTES
[1] Nietzsche’s
works are cited in abbreviated titles (WP
for The Will to Power and BGE for Beyond Good and Evil), followed by the book number, then passage
number.
[2] Deleuze discusses his conception of
immanence in Spinoza in the following: Expressionism
in Philosophy: Spinoza, pp.155-186 and What
is Philosophy?, pp. 35-60. Deleuze
also relates immanence to the “plane of consistency”: “consistency concretely
ties together heterogeneous, disparate, elements as such: it assures the
consolidation of fuzzy aggregates, in other words, multiplicities of the
rhizome type. In effect, consistency,
proceeding by consolidation, acts necessarily in the middle, by the middle, and
stands opposed to all planes of principle or finality. Spinoza, Hölderlin, Kleist, Nietzsche are the
surveyors of such a plane of consistency. Never unifications, never
totalizations, but rather consistencies or consolidations.” A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and
Schizophrenia, p.507. This also explains Nietzsche’s take on the body.
[3] See Smith 1998, pp.
251-252 and Smith 2007, pp.66-78.
Copyright © 2007 Minerva
All rights are reserved, but fair and good faith use
with full attribution may be made of this work for educational or scholarly
purposes.
Paolo Bolańos teaches philosophy at the Faculty
of Arts and Letters, University of Santo Tomas in Manila and is currently a
Postgraduate Research Scholar of the Department of Philosophy, Macquarie
University in Sydney,
Return to Minerva (Volume 11) Main Page
Go to Top of This Page