ISSN
1393-614X Minerva - An Internet Journal of Philosophy Vol. 11 2007
________________________________________________
Aristotle’s
Psychology, Emotion’s Rationality, and Cognition of Being: A Critical Note on
Ogren’s Position Greg
Sadler |
Abstract
Ogren advances a hermeneutic interpretation
of Aristotle that brings to light several important and overlooked points about
Aristotle, emotion, and cognition. In my article, I argue that his
interpretation is on certain points correct, particularly in stressing that the
distinctively human, irrational, emotional and desiring part of the soul is
rational to a certain extent, and through its own forms of cognition,
revelatory of being. His interpretation errs, however, by construing the fully
rational part of the soul in a fundamentally un-Aristotelian way, as merely a
faculty informed by the rules of formal logic. After indicating Ogren’s
interpretation’s strong points, then its central errors, I present an alternate
exegetically grounded Aristotelian interpretation of these matters. Specifically,
I show that Aristotle’s division of the parts of the soul is more complicated
and ambiguous than Ogren’s interpretation. Then, I show that, for Aristotle,
the fully rational part of the soul is, contra Ogren, concerned with practical
matters and life, and possesses substantive modes of cognition of the world. I
finish by exploring one of these, specifically perception of moral qualities,
and discuss some recent Aristotle scholarship engaging this issue.
Brian Ogren’s 2004 article, “Aristotle’s Rhetoric and the Cognition of Being: Human Emotions and the
Rational-Irrational Dialectic,” develops an interesting interpretation of
Aristotle’s moral theory, dealing specifically with the complicated
relationship between rationality and the emotions. Ogren stakes out fertile and
fairly under-appreciated intellectual terrain for his interpretation, grounds
well-located in relation to several more illustrious neighbors. Among them are
Ross’s intellectualist interpretation of Aristotle (shored up by Steven Leighton),
which Ogren rightly critiques, and Fortenbaugh’s now classic work on Aristotle
and the emotions. Following out several Heideggerian leads, Ogren steers
Aristotle in the direction of a decidedly hermeneutic interpretation, a project
of considerable philosophical value and potential.
Working out and presenting his interpretation, however, he sets out a
position on the rational and irrational parts of the soul which while quite
correct in some parts is at odds with close, careful and connected readings of
certain Aristotelian passages Ogren does not seem to have fully taken into
account. The consequence is that, rightly rejecting an overly intellectualist
interpretation which sets emotion within an irrational part of the soul
responsive to but unproductive of cognition and reasoning, he strays to the
opposite extreme, investing the only-partly-rational part of the soul, the seat
of the emotions and the locus of moral virtues, with what he unduly strips away
from the fully rational part of the soul. Another understanding of the
relationship between the emotions and rationality is possible, one more
faithful to Aristotle’s texts, in consonance with and drawing upon significant
insights of other recent commentators, and ultimately better suited for Ogren’s
hermeneutic project, and my aim in this commentary article is to provide what
seems to me such an understanding. My hope is also to provoke further dialogue
on these issues in the forum Minerva
supplies.
I. Points of
Agreement and Appreciation.
Before entering into criticisms of Ogren’s position and exposition of an
alternate position, I would like to briefly note where his article seems not
only correct but quite insightful, in a few cases unpacking his insights bit
further. The first thing to note is that he brings to light a puzzle about
emotion in Aristotle’s moral and psychological theory, namely that in the two
places one would most expect to see full systematic treatments of the emotions,
the De Anima and the Nichomachean (and of course the Eudemian) Ethics, we find nothing of the kind. Instead, the few speculations
about emotion in the De Anima are
carried out from perspective of the “natural philosopher” concerned primarily
with the somatic-physical aspects of being rather than in terms of human
psychological and moral dimensions of being the “dialectical philosopher”
examines (403a27-31). In the Ethics
(as well as in passages of the Politics and
Poetics bearing on emotion),
Aristotle seemingly assumes his audience’s familiarity with and knowledge of
his theory of emotion. Several times in the Nichomachean
Ethics, for instance, he will state that the virtue concerned with anger,
i.e. mildness or gentleness (praotēs)
involves getting several different matters correct in one’s anger, but he
nowhere provides even so much as a partial definition of anger.[1] The only extant location of
a systematic and thorough Aristotelian treatment of emotions lies in Rhetoric bk. II. Ogren persuasively and
importantly argues that the Rhetoric
treatment goes beyond concern with emotions as merely manipulable subjects for
the rhetorician.
Second, he is right to criticize and reject readings of Aristotle
regarding the relationship between the parts of the soul as between a fully
rational part (which for the purposes of this article, except in a few cases,
will be henceforth called RP) which is then listened to or obeyed by an
irrational emotional part (which I shall call EP) that “can be said to ‘share
in a rational principle’ insofar as it is obedient to reason,” but which “is in
itself not a reasoning function and in no way can originate rationality” (2004,
p. 7). The problem Ogren raises is how it is that EP can be entirely
irrational, listening to RP only through “a passive acceptance and ordering of
something provided by an outside cognitive source,” (p. 8) without this
acceptance and ordering becoming “purely subjective and arbitrary”, since EP
“share[s] in the principles of rationality through this acceptance and
ordering,” (p. 10) requiring that EP have its own “intrinsically cognitive type
of discernment” (p. 11). This, in turn, possesses the very important
implication that the type of cognition EP possesses will come in many cases
precisely through the human emotions. It is precisely here that the hermeneutic
direction of Ogren’s interpretation becomes evident. Emotion becomes complex,
perceptive, cognitive, and reflexive, allowing distinctively human awareness of
self and world, and the EP becomes the human being’s fundamental mode of access
to “human existence, or Being in the world, and the human’s awareness thereof.”
(p. 12)
II. The
Central Problem with Ogren’s Interpretation
Ogren frames one of the central problems motivating his paper in terms of
a seeming paradox, which can be framed, rephrasing his expression somewhat into
the enthymeme:
1) rationality is the only
feature unique to humanity,
2) but, there exists a uniquely
human component within the irrational part of the soul.
The problematic, but unstated, conclusion then would be:
3) there is a rational
component within the irrational part of the soul.
This then raises the double question: “how can something that is rational
be part of something that is a-rational, and how can something that is
a-rational consist of something that is rational?” (p. 7). This is a
significant problem to raise within Aristotle’s moral theory, but the strategy
Ogren adopts only partly succeeds because it fails to draw on resources already
in Aristotle’s texts for generating answers. Where it goes wrong, his
interpretation amounts to a reverse image of the mistaken Rossian
interpretation, getting beyond its failures to do justice to the EP, but ultimately
according too much to EP at the RP’s expense.
The failed end-point of Ogren’s interpretation comes in his
characterization of the relationship between the two parts of the soul, in
which he attributes to Aristotle the position that:
[R]ationality is a
complex, uniquely human system that encompasses two separate yet related forms
of cognition. One of these is pure, absolute rationality in the sense of the
rules of formal logic. The other, which contains the emotional faculty, is fundamentally
associated with human existence, or Being in the world, and the human’s
awareness thereof. This ‘irrational’ form of rationality does not categorically
follow the rules of formal logic, but as an awareness of human ‘Being,’ is
fully aware of that uniquely human element of the soul which is rationally
commensurate to formal logic. As such, this irrational form of rationality
stands apart from that pure element of rationality which is formal logic while,
at the same time, it can be influenced and persuaded by it through the means of
“reproof and exhortation” (p. 12)
Now, this is a philosophically interesting, in some respects attractive,
and perhaps on its own grounds coherent position to take on rationality,
emotion, and the soul. But, as we shall see, it is not and could not be
Aristotle’s position. And, given the concepts typically central to accounts
indebted to Aristotle, it cannot even properly be called Aristotelian Unless
Ogren means to signify something quite different from the usual meaning of the
term “formal logic”, the fully rational part of the soul, RP, as Aristotle
characterizes it in his works, simply is not reducible to formal logic. That
textual problem aside, this reduction of RP results in such an impoverishment
that the very notion of RP influencing and persuading EP risks incoherence. The
strategy of taking away from RP to give to EP leads ultimately to an
impoverished Aristotelian understanding even of EP and its determinate modes of
cognition, particularly reflexive ones.
So, we must ask, what is missing from Ogren’s account? What features of
Aristotle’s moral theory could Ogren have taken into account more fully? I
would like to briefly focus on three: the complexity of Aristotle’s conceptual
divisions of the integrated parts of the human soul; the types of rationality
belonging to the fully rational part; and finally, logos, emotion and perception of moral realities. All of these are
components of an alternative, and I would claim more faithfully Aristotelian
interpretation which can also acknowledge and incorporate what is correct in
Ogren’s interpretation.
III.
Aristotle’s conceptual divisions of the parts of the human soul.
There are deep ambiguities which must be acknowledged in Aristotle’s
discussions of the parts of the soul and their rationality. Aristotle expresses
several misgivings in D.A. 432a22-b7
about schemes for dividing the soul into parts, not least of which is that when
adopting a fundamental rational-irrational distinction, locating the sensitive
(aisthētikon), imaginative (phantastikon),
and desiring parts (orektikon) raises
difficulties.[2] Later in D.A. (433a33-b5), he notes,
self-referentially as it turns out, that distinguishing and dividing the soul
into parts according to their powers produces an exuberant number (pampolla) of parts. He names off as
examples nutritive, sensitive, intellectual (noētikon), deliberative (bouleutikon),
desiring, appetitive (epithumētikon)
and irascible (thumikon) parts. Some
of these, given explanations elsewhere, overlap with or are parts of each
other, something worth keeping in mind in looking to Aristotle’s distinctions
of parts of the soul. There are three particularly relevant N.E. discussions, and three Politics discussions.
One N. E. bk. I discussion
(1097b35-98a5) distinguishes four parts
of the soul. Two of these are irrational and not uniquely human:
a) the part concerned with simply nutrition and growth, shared in common
with all living things, even with plants; and
b) the “perceptive” (aisthētikē)
part, shared with animals (but only, as we shall see, “perceptive” in certain
modes of perception).
Two of these are rational and specifically human (to idion):
c) the part that, so to speak, “is obedient to” or “is persuaded by”
reason (hōs epipeithes logōi);
and
d) the part that possesses reason and which thinks discursively (dianōoumenon).
This passage distinguishing two rational parts is suspected as an
interpolation by some commentators. However, if this division in the rational
part would be rejected on that grounds, Aristotle’s characterization of the
rational and specifically human part as a whole, “the part that is concerned
with action [praktikē], and
possesses reason,” would not fit Ogren’s more formal construal of the rational
part. And, given all the other occurrences of the motif of a part participating
in rationality by “listening”, “being persuaded by”, “being obedient to” RP,
there would be little reason not to be able to read such a distinction into the
rational part of the soul.
Another, longer N.E. discussion
Ogren draws on (1102a27-1103a4) postulates first a distinction between the
irrational part (alogon) and the part
possessing reason, but then subdivides both parts, doing so in such a way,
however, as to yield a tripartite distinction. In this passage, the irrational
part of the soul is divided into:
a) the part concerned with simply nutrition and growth, shared in common
with all living things, even with plants; and
b) the (distinctively human) part which “in a way participates in reason”
(1102b14), the “appetitive, and desirous in general” part (epithumētikon kai holōs orektikon, 1102b30-1).
Addressing the paradox Ogren raises, Aristotle suggests that “if it is
necessary to say that [b] possesses reason, then the rational part of the soul will
be twofold” (1103a2-3):
c) the part that possesses reason by participating in
it, “like one listening to a father,” and
d) the part that possesses reason most fully (kuriōs) and in itself
Here we have clearly what I earlier labeled RP and EP, corresponding to
the two parts Ogren discusses.
In another passage from bk. VI (1139a4-16), Aristotle again states that
“the soul has two parts, the one possessing reason, and the other irrational,”
but divides RP:
Let us suppose that there
are two rational parts:
d1) one by which we
contemplate [theōroumen] the
kind of beings whose principles do not admit of being otherwise [mē endekhontai allōs ekhein];
and
d2) one by which we
contemplate beings which do admit being otherwise
These, he goes on to say, can be called the “scientific” (epistēmonikon) and “calculative” or
“reasoning” (logistikon) parts of the
soul. Precisely what the latter consists in, and what it excludes, is not
entirely clear when comparing Aristotelian texts, since in this passage,
Aristotle identifies “reasoning” (logizesthai)
and “deliberation” (bouleuesthai),
the latter of which elsewhere in the two Ethics,
the Politics, and the Rhetoric gets applied not only to
speculative or theoretical matters, but also and especially to practical matters.
In D.A., however, he seems to exclude
from the reasoning part, also called “mind” or “intellect” (nous), any engagement with practical
matters except as objects of contemplation, so that e.g. one can think of
something pleasant with the reasoning part, without that part bidding one to
pursue it, i.e. without any practical reasoning issuing from the reasoning
part.
The Politics provides three
other Aristotelian discussions of the parts of the soul in terms of its
rationality (1333a17-30, 1334b17-29, 1254b7-24), and these complicate but also
enrich the problematic Ogren raises and attempts to resolve. In the first,
there is no discussion of irrational parts. Instead, there is the familiar
distinction between two rational parts, but with several interesting twists.
One part by its very nature (kath’ auto)
possesses reason, while the other part does not by its very nature possess
reason but again is capable of “listening to” or “complying with” reason (logōi . . . hupakouein). It is
interesting to point out, however, that Aristotle introduces yet another
distinction within the part that possesses reason, RP.
And, it is divided [diēirētai]
into two parts, in accordance with the way we are accustomed to divide them. For
reason is on the one hand practical, on the other speculative [theōrētikos]. It is clear that
this part of the soul must then be divided along the same lines. (1333a24-7)
Accordingly, this would give us:
d1) one by which we contemplate,
i.e. engage in speculative reasoning and thinking; and
d2) one by which we engage in
practical reasoning, including deliberation and choice (prohairesis).
Note that these two parts or RP are not immediately identifiable with the two parts of RP distinguished in
the N.E. passage above.
The later Politics passage
(1334b17-28), whose context is the education and development of human beings,
distinguishes simply between an irrational part of the soul and a part
possessing reason, and states that their habitual structures (tas hexeis) are desire (orexis) for the former, and mind or
intellect (nous) for the latter
(1334b19-20), meaning by this presumably properly structured desires in the EP,
and the intellectual virtue or perfection “intellect,” rather than the entirety
of the RP, sometimes rendered in translation as “intellect” or “mind” or (e.g.
in the D.A., 432b26 and ff.
discussion about the motivational power of intellect and desire). He goes on to
lay out one of the “rigid hierarchies” (p. 16) Ogren points out, noting that
the irrational, desiring part exists in children before the rational, reasoning
(ho logismos) part develops, so that
attention or training (epimeleia)
must first be given to the desires, since training of the desires is for the
sake of the mind. Put in terms of the parts of the soul, this irrational,
desirous part must be the part amenable to reason. Aristotle is very usefully
reminding us that its information and ordering by the rational part is not
something guaranteed to happen, requiring attention, care, education, and
discipline to be devoted to the developing human being, these being devoted by
adult beings in whom hopefully the RP and EP have been properly developed.
The third passage is from Aristotle’s infamous discussion of natural
slavery. Of particular interest in this passage is that the same opposition
between intellect (nous) and desire (orexis) in the human being is brought
up. The terminology immediately shifts, however to “the emotional part”, which
ought to be governed by “intellect, and the part possessing reason” (1254b8-9).
In describing the intellectual condition of the “natural slave,” Aristotle also
provides a characterization applicable to EP, namely “participating in reason [koinōnōn logou], so far as to
perceive it [aisthanesthai], though
not to possess it” (1254b22-3). This capacity to “perceive” reason in another
is distinctively human, lacking in other animals, which merely follow their
emotions (1254b23-4). Later, he notes: “the parts of the soul are present in
every person, but they are present in different ways.” What is lacking or
deficient in the natural slave is the deliberative part (1260a11-3), noted
above as the “reasoning” or “calculative part”.
It is vital to take cognizance of three things at this point. First,
since in the longer N.E. passage b)
and c) are in fact the same part, EP, this yields a tripartite distinction, the
distinction Fortenbaugh regarded as Aristotle’s distinctive contribution to
proper understanding of the emotions, and which he explicitly contrasted to a
bipartite, rational-irrational psychology of emotion found in some Aristotelian
works. The passages cited and discussed above have also provided us with fuller
specification of both EP and RP. Second, looking at these passages presenting
divisions of the soul, it seems that Aristotle generally carries out divisions
motivated by the topic under discussion, generating accounts seemingly at odds
with each other in some respects, but reconcilable when they are viewed as partial
perspectives integratable into one coherent account. Never, however, are these
perspectives actually and explicitly integrated in Aristotle’s extant work,
requiring us to engage in interpretation. As to EP specifically, Aristotle
regards it as irrational when looked at in one framework, rational looked at in
another framework. Key here would be asking whether Aristotle always means the
same thing in these passages by the terms “possessing reason” or “rational” (logos ekhon) and “irrational” or perhaps
more aptly translated “without reason” (alogon).
Third, we should also be wary of assuming that the four-part distinction is
entirely reducible to this tripartite distinction, for the animal-perceptive
part of the soul, distinct from the nutritive-growth part of the soul, is
qualitatively different in humans and other animals, as we shall see in section
V.
IV. Types of
Cognition of the Rational Part
What types of cognition does RP engage in? The “absolute rationality in
the sense of the rules of formal logic” (p. 12) Ogren attributes to the fully
rational part could be an object of some of the forms of cognition Aristotle
attributes to it, an object most likely only partly grasped and utilized, since
regarding any concretely existing human RP as “absolute rationality” seems
rather suspect from an Aristotelian perspective. Rationality is, as just
pointed out above, something that requires development in human beings. Setting
considerations about development of rationality and the imperfections of actual
human beings aside, however, a more serious problem arises for Ogren’s
distinction of “two separate yet related forms of cognition” (p. 12),
particularly in the context of N.E. bk
VI.
The problem is really fourfold, i.e. there are four connected features of
RP which according to Ogren’s position it cannot have, but which can be derived
from Aristotle’s texts. First, as noted just earlier, RP includes both
speculative and practical rationality, actualized through developed habits.
Second, for Aristotle even speculative rationality and its associated “mind” or
“thinking”, which may be conceptually extricable from desire and emotion, is
not merely a matter of formal logic, but substantively engages the world it
aims to know. Third, in actual intellectual practice desires and pleasures do
become involved in even the use of RP’s speculative sub-part. Fourth, RP’s
intellectual habit and virtue of phronēsis,
“prudence” or “practical wisdom,” involves a very important type of perception,
a range of cognition Ogren wishes to attribute to EP. In the interests of
brevity, only the first and fourth points will be amplified here.
In Aristotle’s account, RP, the fully rational part of the soul, very
clearly includes not only practical reasoning,
but practical reason, or as he also
puts it practical thought or intellect (dianoia praktikē, and to
praktikon dianoētikon), which he distinguishes from the speculative
intellect. Both of these are intellectual parts of the soul, and each part has
its own specific engagement with truth and falsity, and its own habitually
structured ways of attaining truth, i.e. the intellectual virtues (1139b12-4).
For the theoretical intellect, truth and falsity are fairly straightforward,
but what must be stressed is that the three virtues of even this sub-part of
the soul, its determinate forms of cognition, are in no way reducible to the
rules of formal logic. Simply to take
one example, epistemē,
systematically and logically ordered knowledge, often translated as “science”,
will of course involve the rules of formal logic, but what makes any given epistemē such is that it deals with
a determinate type of beings (beings whose first principles cannot be
otherwise), and that it can be taught and learnt, i.e. systematically arranged
and presented. It is, therefore a substantive, rather than merely formal type
of cognition belonging to RP.
The relationship of the practical intellect to truth is more complicated,
and involves explicit reference to desire and action, what Ogren would
recognize as dimensions of “Being in the world and the human’s awareness
thereof” (p. 12). The work of the practical intellect is to attain “truth
situated in correspondence [homologōs
ekhousa] to right desire” (1139a30-2). Prudence or practical wisdom, “a
true [i.e. truth-attaining or generating] rational [meta logou] habitual structure dealing practically with human
goods” (1140b20-2), is a central virtue of the practical intellect it not only
involves substantive cognitive engagement with being through perception,
inference, evaluation, and action, but also, as Aristotle says, is a
particularly reflexive type of cognition. “Practical wisdom seems to be
especially something concerning oneself, and the individual” (malist’. . . peri auton kai hena,
1141b30-1). In addition to practical wisdom, and setting aside art or skill (tekhnē), Aristotle distinguishes
several other forms of practical cognition belonging to RP in bk. VI:
understanding or good judgement (sunesis),
good apprehension of the equitable (gnōmē),
and cleverness (deinotēs).
In order to assess Ogren’s claims for EP and RP, it is particularly
important to look at several things Aristotle says about practical wisdom.
First, because it involves deliberation and action, practical wisdom requires
apprehension or knowledge of both general principles and of particulars (ta kath’ hekasta, 1141b15-22), which is
why it can and must be acquired and exercised through experience (1142a12-17).
Second, the scope of practical wisdom is very broad, including but not confined
to political science and household management. It is intimately bound up with
the moral virtues (or their lacks or opposites) that structure EP and its ways
of cognition (1144a11-36), in such a way that moral virtues and practical
wisdom require each other in order to develop out of the human being’s natural
capacities. As Aristotle puts it, “Virtue is a habitual structure that is not
only according to right reason [kata
logon] but also cooperating with [meta]
right reason. And practical wisdom is right reason regarding these matters.”
(1144b26-8). Third, practical wisdom involves perception, specifically of the particulars action, deliberation, and choice
is concerned with. This type of perception is not bodily-sense-perception, but
rather something more like the mode of cognition by which we apprehend basic
geometric figures, like it only to a degree, however, since the perception
germane to practical wisdom is of a different kind (allo eidos, 1142a24-31).
V. Perception
of the Distinctively Human Moral World
The mode of perception practical wisdom permits is one important type of
cognition Ogren takes from RP to assign to EP. Here is where again what is
correct and insightful must be carefully distinguished from what is clearly
mistaken in Ogren’s account. He is entirely correct to note the interworking,
even one might say, intertwining, of RP and EP. And, his interpretation rightly
accords to emotion cognitive roles in grasping reality overlooked by overly
intellectualist interpretations of Aristotle. Through adopting a hermeneutic
perspective he also ties these to distinctively human ways of participating in
being, including the reflexivity of human being. He very helpfully stresses
that desire, pleasure, and emotions are integral to the full scope of human rationality.
Lastly, these positive traits of his interpretation accord to the Rhetoric and its key themes a more
important and philosophically rigorous place in the Aristotelian corpus than
many commentators do. As noted earlier, where his interpretation goes wrong is
in assigning so much of this simply to EP at the expense of RP. The main reasons his interpretation develops
in that direction are, I would hazard to guess, are three: 1) failure to see
that Aristotle’s texts accord RP several substantive forms of cognition, human
ways of apprehending concrete being; 2) inadequately taking into account the
central importance of proper structuring, formation, evaluation, and training
of EP’s (and RP’s) desires, emotions, pleasures and pains, particularly through
habituation determined by RP but consolidated in and in part by EP; 3) an
allied failure to notice that the concrete being(s) grasped though uniquely
human cognition is grasped through moral evaluation involving logos as both “reason” and “language,”[3] so that our determinate way
of “Being in the world” is as moral beings.
As just noted, practical wisdom involves perception. An important passage
in the Politics supplies some needed
amplification:
The human being alone among animals
possesses language [logon. . . ekhei].
Voice [phōnē] is a
signaling of the painful and the pleasurable, and so this is something the
other animals can do (for their nature has progressed so far as to have
perception of the painful and the pleasurable and to signal these to each
other), but language is for indicating the useful [to sumpheron] and the harmful [to
blaberon], as well as the just and the unjust. For this is unique to humans
in relation to the other animals, that they alone have perception of the good [agathou] and the bad [kakou], and
the just and the unjust, and of all other such things, and the sharing [koinōnia] in these produces the
household and the city. (1253a10-18)
The “and of all other such things” admits of considerable extension. To
provide one example, two of the three modes of goods and evils the three types
of rhetoric deals in already form part of the listing; to them can be added
epideictic rhetoric’s the “beautiful” or “fine” (to kalon) and the “ugly” or “shameful”. What is particularly
striking about this dense passage is that Aristotle ties together human
language, reason (the undertone of logos as “reason” should not be expunged
from this text), perception, moral qualities, community, and the uniquely
human. At the same time, he does not exclude animals from perception, even
perception of certain moral qualities, i.e. pain and pleasure. Here, we should
hearken back to the four-part division of the human soul, and the disappearance
of the irrational perceptive part in the other divisions. What I suggest is
that the irrational perceptive part is the specifically animal part, which we
do possess, along with (and integrated with, as are all the parts of the soul)
a uniquely human perceptive part amenable to, and thereby participating to some
extent in reason. Our way of grasping the world and the different kinds of
beings, including ourselves, is innumerably richer than mere animal life since
we grasp these through moral evaluations, but this is precisely because our EP
is informed by an RP that, admittedly in most if not all actual human beings in
need of development and liable to some misperceptions, is vastly wider in scope
than the rules of formal logic.
Now, what has been often lost in Aristotle interpretation is something
Ogren rightly calls our attention to, namely that EP’s relation to RP,
analogized to listening to a father or a friend, requires that EP itself
possess a degree of rationality, that it, so to speak, brings something to the
table, rather than just accepting scraps thrown to it by RP. Emotions are a
vital part of how this productive cognitive relation to the world, to self, and
to others takes place, and this can be understood via Heideggerian attunement
or mood informed by understanding, fallenness or falling prey, and articulation
(Heidegger, 1996), or through Aristotelian categories, or as I take Ogren to be
doing, through judicious combination of both, a project also carried out
explicitly in Gadamer (1995). In recent years, a small but very promising
literature specifically on the role of emotion in moral, and specifically human
cognition has developed, and I would like to end my remarks by briefly noting
several of the works following out these lines (although, to my knowledge, none
of these authors seem to have discerned the importance of the just cited Politics passage).
Nancy Sherman’s The Fabric of
Character has been of particular importance, for in it she notes that
Aristotelian ethics requires attention to what she calls the “ethical salience”
(1989, p. 28-44) of particulars in determinate, often ambiguous situations.
This is a matter of perception, precisely the kind of perception we have been
discussing here, perception that involves both RP and EP. For, on the one hand,
“even if without the emotion we could somehow see ethical salience, the way we
see would still be defective and imperfect… The point is that without emotions,
we do not fully register the facts or record them with the sort of resonance
and importance that only emotional involvement can sustain” (p. 47). On the
other, mere emotional response is not enough, since “[p]erception informed by
ethical considerations is the product of experience and habituation” (p. 31).
Gisela Striker likewise notes: “if emotional dispositions are what underlies
virtue of character, the influence of emotions on judgement cannot be regarded
as merely distorting, a distraction, as it were from rational thought… If
morally good people can be expected to have certain characteristic emotional
responses, then the influence of emotion may sometimes be what is needed to see
things in the right way” (1996, p. 297).
Martha Nussbaum, in the essay Ogren cites, does not use precisely the
language of “perception of ethical salience” or “cognition of value”, but does
make an important point about the type of perception implicit in emotions,
which “involve the ascription of significant worth to items in the world
outside of the agent, items that he or she does not fully control” (1996, p.
312). Barbara Koziak’s Retrieving
Political Emotion, Kostas Kalimtzis’s Aristotle
on Political Enmity and Disease, and Marlene Sokolon’s Political Emotions each likewise engage this aspect of Aristotle’s
treatment of emotion. The work that frames this aspect most not only within
Aristotelian ethico-political, psychological, or rhetorical contexts, but
within an explicitly metaphysical one, is Deborah Achtenberg’s Cognition of Value in Aristotle’s Ethics,
in which she argues, among many other valuable points, one on which it is
fitting to end:
For Aristotle, value is not a special moral object beyond those we can
experience or know to which our special moral faculty must be responsive if we
are to have virtue and act appropriately. For him, awareness of value is simply
a cognitive matter. Value is cognized by our two faculties for nondiscursive
awareness, intellectual insight (nous),
and practical insight (phronēsis),
or, as Aristotle often says more simply, value is perceived. It is cognized by
emotion as well, since emotion for Aristotle is not brute but is of itself a
type of perception of value, specifically, perception of the value of certain
particulars. (2002, p. 44)
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Achtenberg, Deborah. (2002) Cognition of Value in Aristotle’s Ethics.
Albany: SUNY Press.
Aristotle. (2000) On the Soul. Cambridge, Harvard
University Press (Loeb Classical Library)
Aristotle. (1998) Politics. Cambridge, Harvard University
Press (Loeb)
Aristotle. (2000) The “Art” of Rhetoric. Cambridge,
Harvard University Press (Loeb)
Aristotle. (1990) The Nichomachean Ethics. Cambridge,
Harvard University Press (Loeb)
Gadamer, Hans-Georg. (1995) Truth and Method, 2nd ed,
revised. Trans. Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall. New York, Continuum.
Heidegger, Martin. (1996) Being and Time. Trans. Joan Stambaugh.
Albany, S.U.N.Y. Press.
Kalimtzis, Kostas (2000) Aristotle on Political Enmity and Disease:
An Inquiry into Stasis. Albany, S.U.N.Y. Press.
Koziak, Barbara. (2000) Retrieving Political Emotion: Thumos,
Aristotle and Gender. University Park, Penn. State University Press.
Nussbaum, Martha Craven (1996),
“Aristotle on Emotions and Rational Persuasion”, in Essays on Aristotle’s Rhetoric, Amélie Oskenberg Rorty, ed.
Berkeley, University of California Press.
Ogren, Brian. (2004) “Aristotle’s
Rhetoric and the Cognition of Being:
Human Emotions and the Rational-Irrational Dialectic,” Minerva, vol. 8.
Sherman, Nancy (1989) The Fabric of Character: Aristotle’s Theory
of Virtue. Oxford, Clarendon.
Sokolon, Marlene. (2006) Political Emotions: Aristotle and the Symphony of Reason and Emotion. DeKalb, Northern
Illinois University
Press.
Striker, Gisela. (1996) “Emotions
in Context: Aristotle’s Treatment of the Passions in the Rhetoric and His Moral Psychology”, in Essays on Aristotle’s Rhetoric, Amélie Oskenberg Rorty, ed.
Berkeley, University of California Press.
Yack, Bernard. (1993) The Problems of a Political Animal:
Community, Justice and Conflict in Aristotelean Political Thought.
Berkeley, University of California Press.
NOTES
[1] Aristotle
does do this in De Anima and several
times in the Topics, each time,
providing a definition to illustrate the act or scope of defining.
[2]. All translations from Aristotle are, unless
otherwise noted, the author’s, who has consulted and where appropriate drawn in
part from those of Ross, Rackham, Freese, Cooper, Kennedy, Hett, Sinclair and
Saunders. Aristotle’s passages are referred to by their Bekker page and line
numbers, which are typically integrated within the texts of more scholarly
English translations. All Greek passages are cited from the Loeb Classical
Library Edition texts.
[3]. Bernard Yack cuts the difference and translates logos in this passage as “reasoned
speech,” providing some good justification for this choice (1993, p. 65). To my
ear, that rendering sounds too restrictedly intellectualist. The human
capacities for perception of and referring to moral qualities does not imply
that we are always reasoning about, or even behaving rationally in relation to
them.
Copyright © 2007 Minerva
All rights are reserved, but
fair and good faith use with full attribution may be made of this work for
educational or scholarly purposes.
Gregory B. Sadler is an Assistant
Professor in Philosophy and Religious Studies at Ball State University,
teaching classes at the Indiana State Prison extension.