ISSN 1393-614X Minerva - An
Internet Journal of Philosophy Vol. 10 2006
____________________________________________________
Heidegger on Gelassenheit Barbara Dalle Pezze
|
Abstract
Martin
Heidegger’s Conversation On A Country
Path About Thinking (1966a) deals with the concept of Gelassenheit experienced as the essence
of thinking, a thinking that is not intended as representing, as
self-determining thinking, but is conceptualized as “meditative thinking.”
Meditative thinking is the kind of thinking that thinks the truth of being, that
belongs to being and listens to it.
To understand Gelassenheit as
the essence of thinking means to have a different and more radical insight into
the essence of who we are. The aim of this paper is to investigate what
Heidegger means by Gelassenheit, but
not proposing an answer to a “what is” question. This paper is instead an
attempt to enact a thinking transformation that through a close reading of
Heidegger’s work will lead us on that path towards Gelassenheit, on which a different
understanding of man’s innermost being can be
glimpsed.
Conversation on a Country Path about
Thinking
One of the major problems we face when
approaching Heidegger’s thought is that we are forced to dwell in uncertainty.
When Heidegger speaks, he does not give any assurance regarding his saying. He
willingly puzzles us; he always tries to undermine and rouse us from our
comfortable thinking zone. And in so doing, Heidegger wants his reader to be
open to something unusual that could occur. This is particularly evident in
Heidegger’s work Conversation on a
Country Path about Thinking (1966a), a work that deals on and with the
essence of thinking investigated as Gelassenheit. That will be the central
focus of the present paper.
Before beginning this paper, I would like
to make a preliminary remark. I am aware that there are many different ways to
approach Heidegger’s thought, and I am also aware of the importance of a
critical reading of it. Nonetheless, before being in the position of putting
forward a critique, it is necessary to spend time and efforts to work through
the complexity and richness of Heidegger’s own thought. The aim of the present
paper, therefore, is not to be a critique of Heidegger’s concept of Gelassenheit – this remains in fact a
task to be developed in a further study. Aim of the present paper is instead, to
be an in depth analysis of Heidegger’s own concept of Gelassenheit. Having said that, let us
now proceed in the investigation.
The Conversation, written between 1944 and
1945, was published for the first time in 1959, together with a “Memorial
Address” that Heidegger delivered in 1955 on the occasion of the 175th birthday
of composer Conradin Kreutzer. The title of the book containing these two works
is Discourse on Thinking (1966b). In
the “Memorial Address,” Heidegger talks about Gelassenheit in relation to technical
devices [technische Dinge]. But, as
von Herrmann (1994) suggests, if we want to understand how Heidegger thinks Gelassenheit in its essential features,
we must consider the Conversation, a
dialogue on the nature of thinking conceived as Gelassenheit.
Heidegger’s Conversation is a dialogue between a
scientist, a scholar and a teacher. The scientist represents one who conducts
scientific research, and who is therefore accustomed to thinking according to a
deductive and representational model of thinking. The scholar represents an
academic “learned in the history of philosophical thought” (Lovitts 1995, p.
599), who thinks from within a metaphysical perspective. The teacher, through
whom Heidegger speaks, we can consider to represent the Heideggerian idea of
‘thinker’. In this dialogue these three speakers conduct an inquiry into the
nature of thinking, a type of thinking that does not involve willing. They
search for a “will-less thinking” (Lovitts 1995, p. 599) that will be found to
occur as ‘Gelassenheit’.
At the beginning of the dialogue the
scientist and the scholar appear to deal with the search in accordance with
their scientific way of thinking, which is to say thinking with the mindset
proper to their scientific role and speaking from well determined and clear
positions. But gradually, under the guidance of the teacher, the interlocutors
begin to give up their own standpoints and, with that, their accustomed form of
thinking. They let the dialogue itself take charge, so to speak. As they abandon
the will to dictate and lead the search, a different approach and way of
thinking discloses itself through the dialogue. The interlocutors, as the
dialogue proceeds, no longer impose their view, but let the elements of their
search emerge from their dialogue with one another. In the Conversation the standpoint of the
single speakers is gradually abandoned, in the sense that the focus is on what
is disclosed during the dialogue by and through the interaction of the three
speakers. We could venture to say that, at a certain point, it does not matter
anymore who said what, because what reveals itself in the dialogue is beyond the
distinction of ‘whatness’. What the Conversation shows is the transformed
nature of thinking, in its transforming process. During the Conversation
we witness in the interaction between the three speakers what I would call
the transforming transformation of our own way of thinking, which is forced to
change in its core in order to be part of the scene settled by
Heidegger.
Heidegger’s Conversation does not present a linear
structure. We do not find a form of deductive reasoning that brings the dialogue
forth. Rather, we witness and experience a continuous circular movement. In the
dialogue we do not find a series of stages that takes us closer to the goal we
are aiming at. In the dialogue it is possible, instead, to recognize
hermeneutical circles that are nourished by the dialogue itself. The dialogue,
that is, the interplay between the
interlocutors, shows the movement and counter-movement that constitutes the
structure of the dialogue as the expanse in which it occurs, as the experience
of Gelassenheit. That is why we can
say that, at every moment of the dialogue, what we are looking for is already
showing itself, and the investigation itself is already an experience of
it.
Now, the aim of the present paper is to
investigate what Heidegger means by Gelassenheit through a careful study of
the Conversation. To reach this goal,
I will firstly present the difference between our common way of thinking and
meditative thinking. I shall then explore the first step needed to move towards
Gelassenheit, that is, what Heidegger
indicates as “keeping awake” for Gelassenheit. I will look, then, at Gelassenheit as “higher acting” and
“waiting”. After that I will contend with the dialogue form chosen by Heidegger
for this search. Finally, I shall introduce Heidegger’s concept of Gegnet and its relation to Gelassenheit.
This investigation, however, remains an
interpretation that, as such, does not pretend to be exhaustive, though I hope
it will give a valuable contribution to the understanding of Heidegger’s thought
on Gelassenheit.
Meditative
Thinking
When we use the word ‘thinking’, our
thought immediately goes back to a well known set of definitions that we have
learnt in our life or in our studies. To us thinking is a mental activity that
helps us to solve problems, to deal with situations, to understand circumstances
and, according to this understanding, to take action in order to move forward.
Thinking for us also means to have an opinion, to have an impression that
something is in a certain way. Thinking means reasoning, the process of reaching
certain conclusions through a series of statements. Thinking is “a means of
mastery” (Lovitts 1995, p. 586).
We already mentioned that this is a paper
about the essence of thinking, sought as Gelassenheit. But the kind of thinking
whose essence we are about to investigate is not the common way of thinking. The
kind of thinking that we need to think of is “the thinking of the thinker.” This
is not a general philosophical concept of thinking, but we need to consider
what, in the Discourse, Heidegger
calls “meditative thinking” [das
besinnliche Denken].
The kind of thinking we are probably
accustomed to is what Heidegger names “calculative thinking” [das rechnende Denken] (1966b, p. 46),
and it is the thinking proper to the sciences and economics, which we, belonging
to the technological age, mainly — if not solely — employ. Calculative thinking,
says Heidegger, “calculates,” “plans and investigates” (1966b, p. 46); it sets
goal and wants to obtain them. It “serves specific purposes” (ibid., p. 46); it
considers and works out many new and always different possibilities to develop.
Despite this productivity of a thinking that “races from one aspect to the
next”; despite the richness in thinking activities proper to our age, and
testified by the many results obtained; despite our age’s extreme reach in
research activities and inquiries in many areas; despite all this, nevertheless,
Heidegger states that a “growing thoughtlessness” (1966b, p. 45) is in place and
needs to be addressed. This thoughtlessness depends on the fact that man is “in flight from thinking” (ibid., p. 45).
“Thoughtlessness” [Gedankenlosigkeit], Heidegger
states,
is an uncanny
visitor who comes and goes everywhere in today’s world. For nowadays we take in
everything in the quickest and cheapest way, only to forget it just as quickly,
instantly. Thus one gathering follows on the heels of another. Commemorative
celebrations grow poorer and poorer in thought. Commemoration and
thoughtlessness are found side by side. (1966b, p. 45)
Calculative thinking, despite being of
great importance in our technological world, is a thinking “of a special kind.”
It deals, in fact, with circumstances that are already given, and which we take
into consideration, to carry out projects or to reach goals that we want to
achieve. Calculative thinking does not pause to consider the meaning inherent in
“everything that is”. It is always on the move, is restless and it “never
collects itself” (Heidegger 1966b, p. 46). This fact hides and shows that man is
actually “in flight from thinking.” Now, if it is not a question of calculative
thinking, then what kind of thinking does Heidegger refer to when he speaks of
“meditative thinking”? And why, if at all, is there a need for it? Because if we
have no problem in understanding the importance of calculative thinking, we
probably are not so clear about the need, for our existence, of a different kind
of thinking.
In the “Memorial Address,” Heidegger speaks
of two kinds of thinking: the above mentioned “calculative thinking” and
“meditative thinking” (1966b, p. 46). Meditative thinking is a kind of thinking
man is capable of, it is part of his nature; but nevertheless it is a way of
thinking that needs to be awoken. When Heidegger states that man is “in flight from thinking” (1966b, p. 45),
he means flight from meditative thinking. What distinguishes meditative thinking
from calculative thinking? What does meditative thinking mean? It means to
notice, to observe, to ponder, to awaken an awareness of what is actually taking
place around us and in us.
Meditative thinking does not mean being
detached from reality or, as Heidegger says, “floating unaware above reality”
(1966b, p. 46). It is also inappropriate to consider it as a useless kind of
thinking, by stating that it is of no use in practical affairs or in business.
These considerations, Heidegger states, are just “excuses” that, if on one hand
appears to legitimize avoiding any engagement with this kind of thinking, on the
other hand attests that meditative thinking “does not just happen by itself any
more than does calculative thinking” (1966b, p. 46-47). Meditative thinking
requires effort, commitment, determination, care, practice, but at the same
time, it must “be able to bide its time, to await as does the farmer, whether
the seed will come up and ripen” (Heidegger 1966b, p. 47).
Meditative thinking does not estrange us
from reality. On the contrary, it keeps us extremely focused on our reality, on
the hic et nunc of our being,
‘existence’. To enact meditative thinking, Heidegger says that we need to
dwell on what
lies close and meditate on what is closest; upon that which concerns us, each
one of us, here and now; here, on this patch of home ground; now, in the present
hour of history. (1966b, p. 47)
By remaining focused on the moment, we
“notice” aspects of our reality and we keep them in mind. We then “remember”
elements, events, circumstances related to them. This invite us to “think
further”, and by doing so we clarify, discern, elements that pertain to our
situation. Through this process we “grow thoughtful”, and this generates
questions that further deepen our thinking and awareness of the roots of what
moved us to think; and that was just something barely noticed before. An attempt
to enact meditative thinking is carried out by Heidegger himself when, during
the "Memorial Address," he tries to conduct the audience from a situation where
they are passive 'consumers' of the address to a situation in which they
actually meditate and think about what is going on, beyond the simple event of
commemoration. What follows is a long quotation which I think can give us a
picture of what the process of meditative thinking is about:
What does
this celebration suggest to us, in case we are ready to meditate? Then we notice
that a work of art has flowered in the ground of our homeland. As we hold this
simple fact in mind, we cannot help remembering at once that during the last two
centuries great poets and thinkers have been brought forth from the Swabian
land. Thinking about it further makes clear at once that Central Germany is
likewise such a land, and so are
We grow
thoughtful and ask: does not the flourishing of any genuine work depend upon its
roots in a native soil? Johann Peter Hebel once wrote: “We are plants which —
whether we like to admit it to ourselves or not — must with our roots rise out
of the earth in order to bloom in the ether”…
The poet
means to say: For a truly joyous and salutary human work to flourish, man must
be able to mount from the depth of his home ground up into ether. Ether here
means the free air of the high heavens, the open realm of the
spirit.
We grow more
thoughtful and ask: does this claim of Johann Peter Hebel hold today? Does man
still dwell calmly between heaven and earth? Does a meditative spirit still
reign over the land? Is there still a life-giving homeland in whose ground man
may stand rooted…? (Heidegger 1966b, p. 47-48)
Even though “man is a thinking, that is, a meditating being” [der Mensch das denkende, d.h. sinnende Wesen ist]
(ibid., p. 47), we need to train ourselves in the ability to think meditatively,
to confront reality, and thus ourselves, in a meditative way. The cost of not
doing so would be, Heidegger states, to remain a “defenseless and perplexed
victim at the mercy of the irresistible superior power of technology” (ibid., p.
52-53). We would be – and today, more so than sixty years ago, when Heidegger
gave this speech – victims of “radio and television,” “picture magazines” and
“movies”; we would be, and perhaps already are, “chained” to the imaginary world
proposed by these mediums, and thus homeless in our own home:
all that with
which modern techniques of communication stimulate, assail, and drive man – all
that is already much closer to man today than his fields around his farmstead,
closer that the sky over the earth, closer than the change from night to day…
(Heidegger 1966b, p. 48)
The risk for man is to be uprooted not only
from his reality, from his world, but also from himself. If we think
meditatively, however, we allow ourselves to be aware of the risk implied in the
technological age and its usefulness, and we can hence act upon it.
When we think meditatively we do not
project an idea, planning a goal towards which we move, we do not “run down a
one-track course of ideas” (ibid., p. 53). When we think meditatively, we need
to “engage ourselves with what at first sight does not go together at all”
(ibid., p.53). In order to understand what this means, Heidegger suggests that
we look at the comportment we have towards technological devices. We recognize
that, in today’s world technological machineries are indispensable. We need just
to think of computers and their usage in daily life activities to be convinced,
above any doubt, that “we depend on technical devices” (Heidegger 1966b, p.53).
By thinking calculatively, we use these machineries at our own convenience; we
also let ourselves be challenged by them, so as to develop new devices that
would be more suitable for a certain project or more accurate in the carrying
out of certain research.
If calculative thinking does not think
beyond the usefulness of what it engages with, meditative thinking would notice
and become aware of the fact that these devices are not just extremely useful to
us. It would also notice that they, by being so extremely useful, at the same
time are “shackling” us: “suddenly and unaware we find ourselves so firmly
shackled to these technical devices that we fall into bondage to them” (ibid.,
p. 53-54). If man, not being aware of this, is in a situation of being chained
to these machineries, then by becoming conscious of this he finds himself in a
different relation to them. He becomes free of them. With this awareness man can
utilize these instruments just as instruments, being at the same time free to
“let go of them at any time” (ibid., p. 54). And this is so because once we
acknowledge that their usefulness implies the possibility for us to be chained
to them, we deal with them differently; we “deny them the right to dominate us,
and so to wrap, confuse, and lay waste our nature” (ibid., p.54). It is a matter
of a different comportment towards them; it is a different disposition to which
Heidegger gives the name “releasement
toward things” [die Gelassenheit zu
den Dingen] (ibid., p.54)
Releasement toward things is an expression
of a change in thinking. Thinking is not just calculation, but ponders the
meaning involved and hidden behind what we are related to and engaged with. This
hidden meaning, even if it remains obscure as such, is nevertheless detected –
by a meditating thinking – in its presence, a presence that “hides itself.” But,
as Heidegger states,
if we
explicitly and continuously heed the fact that such hidden meaning touches us
everywhere in the world of technology, we stand at once within the realm of that
which hides itself from us, and hides itself just in approaching us. That which
shows itself and at the same time withdraws is the essential trait of what we
call the mystery. I call the comportment which enables us to keep open to the
meaning hidden in technology, openness to
the mystery. (1966b, p. 55)
“Releasement towards things” and “openness
to the mystery” are two aspects of the same disposition, a disposition that
allows us to inhabit the world “in a totally different way.” But as we already
mentioned, this disposition does not just happen to us. It develops through a
“persistent courageous thinking” (ibid., p. 56), which in this work is
meditative thinking.
We have spoken here of meditative
thinking as that mode of thinking that allows “releasement toward things” and
“the openness to the mystery” hidden in the technological world. Let us now move
on, armed with meditative thinking, to further investigate Gelassenheit – which we just glimpsed in
relation to technological devices – in its essential traits, considering it as
“the manner of taking place of a thinking that is wholly free, wholly open to
Being’s governance” (Lovitts 1995, p. 544).
Keeping Awake for Gelassenheit
The dialogue on Gelassenheit opens by addressing the
question of the essence of man. Since the European philosophical tradition has
always seen in thinking the sign of the essence of man, questioning the essence
of thinking means questioning the essence of man. What is investigated as the
essence of man in the Conversation is
not a general meaning of this essence; rather, what is investigated is “the historical self-transforming, essential sway [künftigen Wesen] of man” (F.-W. von Herrmann 1994, p. 373).[1] What is distinctive about this search is
the fact that it can be carried on and experienced only by turning one’s sight
away from man. This seems to be paradoxical, but as von Herrmann states, this
ceases to be a paradox when we consider that the “future” essence of man (which
is what we are looking for) determines itself from its relation to that which is
not man. This means that the “self-transforming essential sway of man is comprehensible
only in that relation from out of which man receives its essential sway” (1994, p. 373),[2] and that, we shall see, is
the relation of Gelassenheit to “Gegnet”, that is, “that-which-regions,”
which is another name for be-ing itself.
As Heidegger states, the traditional
concept of thinking intends thinking as a representing, and therefore as
belonging to the context of will. It is still involved with a subjectivism that
Gelassenheit wants to overcome.
Subjectivism, as Caputo attests, is “setting up the thinking ‘subject’ as the
highest principle of Being, and subordinating everything to the dictates and
demands of the subject” (1990, p. 175). Gelassenheit, as the essence of future thinking, does
not belong to the realm of willing. What characterizes the search carried out in
Heidegger’s Conversation is the fact
that the context of the search requires distance and detachment from the
traditional context in which thinking is related to willing. The question of the
essence of thinking, posed in terms of Gelassenheit, is in fact a question
about the essence of thinking as a “non-willing” [Nicht-Wollen]:
Scholar: But
thinking, understood in the traditional way, as re-presenting is a kind of
willing; Kant, too, understands thinking this way when he characterizes it as
spontaneity. To think is to will, and to will is to
think
Scientist: Then the
statement that the nature of thinking is something other than thinking means
that thinking is something other than willing.
Teacher: And that is
why, in answer to your question as to what I really wanted from our meditation
on the nature of thinking, I replied: I want non-willing. (Heidegger 1966a, p.
58-59)
“I want non-willing” is the first step
towards Gelassenheit. But in this
statement we immediately notice an ambiguity: on the one hand, when one says “I
want non-willing”, it is still a matter of will, wanting the non-willing is an
act of will, as it expresses the will to say no to will. On the other hand,
Heidegger states that, by saying that I want “non-willing,” I mean that I
“willingly … renounce willing” (1966a, p. 59). But by renouncing this, I search
for what overall stays beyond any kind of willing, and that cannot be ‘reached’
by any act of will. By “renouncing willing,” Heidegger states, “we may release,
or at least prepare to release, ourselves to the sought-for essence of a
thinking that is not willing” (1966a, p. 59-60). By means of willing not to
will, we put ourselves in the condition of being able to reach that thinking
that is not a matter of will. As Caputo puts forward, we need to go through this
stage, as it is a “preparation for the final stage of releasement where we have
left the sphere of willing behind altogether, where man, as with Eckhart, has no
will at all.” (1990, p. 171).
By willing not to will, we move one step
closer to Gelassenheit. Letting go of
our willing is the first step that allows Gelassenheit to “wake up” [Erwachen] in ourselves. It is not,
though, that we act to wake it up. Actually this is not at all a waking up. As
Heidegger points out, it is an “awakening of releasement,” in the sense of
“keeping awake for releasement” [Wachbleiben für die Gelassenheit ]
(1966a, p. 61). Keeping awake for Gelassenheit means to let-go of willing,
in order to contribute to the “awakening” of Gelassenheit. But not only that. By
letting-go of willing, we let ourselves be in the position of being let-in into
Gelassenheit. What we face here is a
twofold mode of releasement: from one side we need to let-go of thinking as a
representing that tends to explain everything in terms of reasons. This
letting-go means that we keep ourselves awake for releasement which, on the
other side, means that we open ourselves to something, a ‘mystery’ that – as we
shall see later – is actually be-ing itself, and is that which lets us in into
Gelassenheit.
Heidegger opts to say “keeping awake” [Wachbleiben] for Gelassenheit instead of “to wake up” [Erwachen] Gelassenheit, because the latter implies
an action undertaken by man, and thus implies that a will is still in place, and
that we still abide in the realm of willing. But in order to know what Gelassenheit means, it itself has to be
allowed to be. It is not us that ‘wake it up’. It is something else; from
somewhere else is Gelassenheit called
to be, is ‘let-in’ in ourselves. What we can do is to keep awake for Gelassenheit. Once we free ourselves
from willing, we prepare ourselves for the “awakening of releasement”; the more
we detach ourselves and we “wean ourselves from willing,” the more we contribute
to the “awakening of releasement.”
Posed in these terms, it seems that dealing
with Gelassenheit means to deal with
something specific, something that we would be able to discover and point at,
once we possess the right elements. But, as Heidegger often affirms, we need to
start from what we know and are familiar with, in order to step forward, or to
simply move on.[3] Let us, therefore, accept for now this
impression regarding Gelassenheit,
but try at the same time to keep in mind that Gelassenheit is not something that, as
such, we will be in a position to determine clearly, and hence define as a
whole. It will continue to be hermeneutically the same and something different,
and that will perhaps let us abide in a kind of secure vagueness,[4] in which our thinking will be at rest and
dwell. Having said that, we need to nevertheless focus on specific meanings that
we know, which during the dialogue will be enriched, and perhaps changed, with
that which is unspoken and ‘unseen’, which will give them new flavor, new
sounds, new color.
At this stage, however, we still cannot say
what Gelassenheit is. Grasping the
meaning will be a gradual process of disclosure that arises during the dialogue.
Nevertheless, here we come across the structural moment of Gelassenheit, which shows Gelassenheit as the letting go of
willing, a letting go that prepares us to “let-oneself-in” [Sich einzulassen] into Gelassenheit. Gelassenheit awakens when we let go of
willing, and by letting go of it, we let ourselves in, in the sense that we are
let-in into Gelassenheit. By
letting-go of willing, we actually give ourselves the possibility of being open
to Gelassenheit and, in Gelassenheit, remain open for be-ing
itself. This is also a step that moves us from thinking as a matter of willing
to meditative thinking: it is a “transition from willing into releasement”
(1966a, p. 61).
Now, what does Gelassenheit mean? What do we keep awake
for? What do we let emerge in ourselves, which kind of mindfulness do we awaken,
by letting-go of our thinking as a matter of will? How are we to think Gelassenheit?
Higher Acting and
Waiting
Reading the Conversation, we never find a clear statement that
gives a definition of Gelassenheit.
From our perspective, Gelassenheit is
in fact a process, a conquest, a movement that changes our attitude, our way of
thinking. While reading the conversation we come across elements that belong to
Gelassenheit, but they are not
exhaustive. They lead to a better comprehension of its meaning, but they do not
define a picture of it, one which we could say: that is Gelassenheit. Nevertheless, these
elements point towards and constitute its meaning.
At a certain point of the dialogue we come
across one of these elements. It is identified in the fact that, in Gelassenheit, is “concealed” an acting
which is “higher” than the acting we find in “actions within the
world”:
Scholar: Perhaps a
higher acting is concealed in releasement than is found in all the actions
within the world and in the machinations of all
mankind…
Teacher… which higher acting is yet no
activity.
Scientist: Then
releasement lies — if we may use the word lie — beyond the distinction between
activity and passivity…
Scholar:... because
releasement does not belong to the
domain of the will. (Heidegger 1966a, p. 61).
Before continuing, let me stress one point
that could appear strange. Heidegger refers to Gelassenheit as “higher acting” and
this, at first sight, could appear a contradiction if we consider the word Gelassenheit. The word Gelassenheit has its root on the verb
“lassen” which means to let, to give
something up. This could suggest that an idea of passiveness belongs to Gelassenheit, but this is certainly not
the case. Actually, the whole dialogue, which is an attempt to lead the reader
to experience Gelassenheit, implies,
paradoxically, an active reading. It is an active reading because what this
conversation is about is the letting go of an accustomed way of thinking and
wanting, an experience of something which lies beyond it. This apparent
passivity, which should be ‘enacted’ in the reading and constitutes the
experience of Gelassenheit, is no passivity at all. Indeed, it is a
“higher acting” that, as we shall see, has the form of “waiting.” The enactment
of our thinking, in the attempt to think Gelassenheit, is in itself “higher
acting,” for in its being ‘on the way’ our thinking is a “waiting upon” what we
do not know yet. Our attempt to think Gelassenheit is, therefore, already an
enactment of the higher acting that is proper to Gelassenheit. But now, how are we to
understand this “higher acting”?
Probably when we hear the word “acting” we
immediately relate it to a familiar concept of action, such as the one that
thinks of action as that which produces some kind of result, which means that we
understand action in terms of cause and effect. To understand what Heidegger
means by “higher acting,” we need to refer to the essential meaning that,
according to Heidegger, pertains to ‘action’. In the Letter on Humanism
(1998b), Heidegger defines
the essence of action as “accomplishment”, and he unfolds the meaning of
accomplishment as “to unfold something into the fullness of its essence, to lead
it forth into this fullness – producere” (1998b, p. 239). “Higher
acting” is not, therefore, an undertaking towards a practical doing, but is a
‘higher’ acting as accomplishment, in the sense of leading forth something into
the fullness of its essence. Releasement itself is what makes this available to
man.
Gelassenheit as “higher acting” is
further determined in the dialogue as “waiting” [warten]. As Heidegger affirms, what can
be done to glimpse Gelassenheit is to
actually do nothing but “wait,” “we are to do nothing but wait” [Wir sollen nichts tun sondern warten]
(1966a, p. 62). “Waiting” is the key experience, for in waiting we are in the
position of crossing from thinking as representing to thinking as meditative
thinking. In waiting we move from that thinking which, as Heidegger states, has
lost its “element” (be-ing) and dried up, to the thinking that is “appropriated”
by its “element” (be-ing itself) and which, therefore, has turned towards be-ing
itself (1998b, p. 240-241).
But let us consider more closely the idea
implied in ‘waiting’. When Heidegger says that we have to do nothing but wait,
we probably ask ourselves: what do we have to wait for? Asking this question
puts us back into the realm of representing, and therefore removes us from that
disposition from out of which we can experience Gelassenheit. If we ask what we are
waiting for, we are expecting something, we already have an object of
expectation, whereas we need to remain open towards something we do not know. If
I expect, I have an object of my expectation, whereas ‘waiting’ has no object.
In waiting, we rest in the act of waiting, or as Fabris (1983) states, “waiting
does not objectify, does not reify possibilities, but instead it maintains them
open as possibilities.”[5] As soon as we represent, says Heidegger,
we think about what we are waiting for, and as soon we think about this, we are
not waiting anymore: “in waiting we leave-open what we are waiting for” (1966a,
p. 68) because waiting allows itself to be brought into the openness.
Waiting is a moment of crossing; in waiting
the swinging movement between the different kinds of thinking is present. In
waiting something opens. What we need to do is ‘just’ wait, wait without
expecting.
It seems as though waiting is a moment of
disorientation, which somehow shakes us because it wants us to suspend any kind
of thinking as representing, and therefore any kind of wanting in the sense of
expecting. Waiting is similar to being suspended, lifted up in a moment where
nothing more passes, but just the moment occurs. But if we are to wait and
suspend our expectations, are we still thinking? How do we get to know the
essence of that thinking we are trying to grasp? Everything seems
vague.
If we are disoriented about what Heidegger
says, we are in the right disposition to be open towards what is going to come
towards us. What Heidegger names here is ‘something’ that allows itself to be
thought only by a thinking that is not representing, not a putting forward of
concepts that one knows, in a structured thinking that already means something
to me. To do this would prevent us from sensing the echo of ‘something’
different that is turning toward us. How can we identify this ‘disposition’? We
cannot describe it, as to describe it would mean to have already clear in front
of me what I am describing. If we are in the condition of feeling the urge to
ask these questions to ourselves, says Heidegger, we are getting closer to that
disposition from out of which we are let-in into the essence of thinking. In
waiting we let-go of an accustomed way of thinking, and we let-in what we are
‘waiting upon’, be-ing in its truth. We could venture to say that Gelassenheit names the relation between
Dasein and be-ing. In Gelassenheit,
man, letting go of willing, opens himself, in waiting, to be-ing. In waiting we
are open to be-ing itself and in being open to it, be-ing itself is let be and
we are let-in into Gelassenheit.
In this dialogue, Heidegger never gives the
kind of answer we would expect, the kind of answer that would in fact help us in
not thinking anymore. This kind of
answer would seem to give us clearness, the absence of doubt that would allow us
be quiet and give us the certainty of possessing knowledge regarding that
particular matter. But this is exactly what Heidegger wants to avoid. He wants
us to keep thinking, to be restless, in order to remain open to what occurs, and
in fact he chooses the dialogue form to conduct us towards this openness. Before
dealing with the importance of the dialogue form, let me briefly recall what we
have been saying.
Until now we have characterized Gelassenheit as our disposition in terms
of “keeping awake” for Gelassenheit.
This disposition is open when we let go of thinking as willing. Gelassenheit “awakens when our nature is
let-in so as to have dealings with that which is not willing” (Heidegger 1966a,
p. 61). To let-go of willing awakens Gelassenheit, which in turns reveals
itself as a let-oneself-in into releasement, a releasement in which one would be
“freed of that task of weaning” (ibid., p.60). Gelassenheit, is further characterized
as “higher acting,” which is not to be conceived as an action undertaken for a
practical making or doing, but is to be taken in the sense of ‘waiting’. We have
determined this waiting not as a waiting for something, but as a waiting that
does not expect, because it does not know what to expect. It waits upon
something which is ‘beyond’ man’s will. It is a waiting upon be-ing itself,
which gifts itself to man’s thinking, and toward which (be-ing) Dasein in
releasement remains open.
Our efforts have been an attempt to free
ourselves from thinking in terms of representing, to leap into meditative
thinking. In so doing, we have approached (we have been getting closer to) that
disposition that we are investigating. Gelassenheit is not primarily something
to be described, but is above all something to be experienced, that is to be
discovered and learned. Gelassenheit
is not an event that happens to us, and we just acknowledge it. Gelassenheit occurs as something that
needs to be allowed to happened. To do this we need to undergo a process of
change in the way in which we understand ourselves, and thus in our being a
‘thinking being’. The question we should pose now is not, therefore, what Gelassenheit is, but how can we dwell in
that disposition in which Gelassenheit occurs and holds sway. How
do we let this experience occur? “Through the way of the conversation” [Durch den Gang des Gespräches] (1966a,
p. 69), Heidegger says. The dialogue is, in fact, conducting us to that
‘waiting’ in which Gelassenheit holds
sway.
The Dialogue Form
The possibility of reaching Gelassenheit is offered by the fact that
what is sought for is not known, is hidden and therefore not representable as
something that we already know. Throughout the conversation, Heidegger tries to
allow something to emerge that the dialogue, in its evolving, has been building
up and disclosing. Indeed, it is the dialogue itself which leads us on that
path: “the conversation brings us to that path which seems nothing else than
releasement itself” (Heidegger 1966a, p.70).
Is this the reason why Heidegger uses the
dialogue form to conduct this search? What happens in a dialogue, in a
conversation between people, that does not occur when I think by myself? Is an
open space let open amongst people when they engage in dialogue? Is it in the
expanse, in this ‘meanwhile’ that originates and unfolds when people ‘talk’,
that the openness itself unfolds? Is it in the dialogue (a ‘swaying’ of people’s
thinking) that something existing, but otherwise not unfolding, is first
revealed ? In the dialogue our receptiveness opens up and we become more
prepared to wait. The tendency of affirmation weakens and the truth of what
occurs finds its way to us. During a conversation ‘something else’ is allowed to
be; it regains its time and space in our existence. It is created through the
dialogue, like a symphony. The dialogue is a dynamic game of references, of
signs, that allows new paths of thought, paths that are continuously questioned
concerning their certainty. This means undermining the authority of what is well
known, to let be the multidimensionality of what exists and surrounds us as an
expanse, a vastness of silent notes.
In what follows here is a long quote from
the Conversation, which I believe
could be useful for understanding this dinamic of the dialogue, that we could
say enacts the meditative thinking process:
(Scientist): In many
respects it is clear to me what the word releasement should not signify for us.
But at the same time, I know less and less what we are talking about. We are
trying to determine the nature of thinking. What has releasement to do with
thinking?
(Teacher): Nothing if
we conceive thinking in the traditional way as re-presenting. Yet perhaps the
nature of thinking we are seeking is fixed in
releasement.
(Scientist): With the
best of will, I can not re-present to myself this nature of
thinking.
(Teacher): Precisely
because this will of yours and your mode of thinking as re-presenting prevent
it.
(Scientist): But then,
what in the world am I to do?
(Scholar): I am asking
myself that too.
(Teacher): We are to
do nothing but wait
(Scholar): That is
poor consolation.
(Teacher): Poor or
not, we should not await consolation -something we would still be doing if we
became disconsolate.
(Scientist): Then what
are we to wait for? And where are we to wait? I hardly know anymore who and
where I am.
(Teacher): None of us
knows that , as soon as we stop fooling ourselves
(Scholar): And yet we
still have our path?
(Teacher): To be sure.
But by forgetting it too quickly we give up thinking. (Heidegger 1966a, p.
62)
A conversation confuses. You do not have
‘control’ of what you mean, because the interlocutor may be far removed from the
meaning you have in mind. The interlocutor’s approach to your thought forces you
to question your statements, your beliefs, far beyond your own interpretations.
It forces you to be open to different perspectives. In a conversation that wants
to deal with essential matters, such as the one we are engaging with, we do not
look for clarifications, definitions or agreements on how to define Gelassenheit. We could say that this
dialogue wants to be free from content: it looks for an ‘open space’ where what
we are looking for does not need to be defined against some other concept. In
this openness the truth of that which is appears, and does not need to be
justified, but just let-in in its essential clarity of being.
The fact that the meaning sought is not
accessible as something determined and determinable in one definition, makes the
dialogue form extremely important. The three speakers, occupying different
‘thinking spaces’, create and at the same time reach openness otherwise not
accessible. This brings with it hints and sights that create different sparks of
awareness, and therefore leads to a new openness and vision. This new openness
and vision prepares us to come closer to an otherwise inaccessible awareness
through a continuous resting movement, which is a swinging from one interlocutor
to the other, in a creative relation. Having said that, we now know that, in the
course of this dialogue, something has been happening, in what is said, as well
as beyond and before it. To be aware of this swinging movement is our first
experience of thinking as Gelassenheit.
Until now we have seen that the path
leading to Gelassenheit implies a
letting-go of our own will, and this opens up to us the possibility of
letting-oneself-in into Gelassenheit.
We have spoken of Gelassenheit as a
“higher acting” and we have explained its meaning by saying that this higher
acting is in fact a “waiting upon.” We then further expanded our context
disclosing the ‘expanse’ into which this experience occurs. This ‘expanse’ is
opened through the conversation. Through it, this openness is allowed to be, is
disclosed, and from out of it what we have been saying takes form and something
from the backdrop begins to show. Do we begin to glimpse a new
“horizon”?
Horizon and Region
When we hear the word horizon, we probably
imagine the line that we see far away when we look out at the ocean. It defines
the space within which we see things.
The horizon is the space within which we
represent the objects around us. According to Heidegger, the horizon is not just
this. This perception, he states, is only the side facing us of the openness
that the horizon is.
The horizon is experienced through the
objects that are within it, and actually it can be determined only in relation
to objects and through the fact of representing it to us. The reason for
pointing this out, Heidegger says, is to stress the fact that man has no
experience of what the horizon actually is. We experience objects that we see in
a horizon; but we have no experience of the horizon itself. Not only do we not
recognize it, but “what lets the horizon be what it is has not yet been
encountered at all” (Heidegger 1966a, p. 64). It seems as though here we face
three different elements: objects, the horizon and that which lets the horizon
be.
Assuming that we know what we mean by
objects, let us focus on the latter two elements: the horizon that is an
openness, and the being-open of the horizon, its openness, that does not appear
or that appears, but is not identified. Given this, says Heidegger, according to
our thinking as representing, the ‘being horizon’ of the horizon [Horizonhafte] is just that side of the
openness that faces us, an openness that is all around us, and that is filled up
with the “appearances of what to our re-presenting are objects” (1966a, p. 64).
Being the horizon, the openness that surrounds us, is revealed as something else
besides the field of vision that we perceive. But, says Heidegger, “this
something else is the other side of itself, and so the same as itself” (ibid.,
p. 63). In speaking about the horizon we have performed a ‘step back’ in
thinking. From a thinking dimension closer to Gelassenheit we are now back,
considering how we represent to ourselves the concept of horizon. From here, we
begin another hermeneutical journey towards a transformed meaning of horizon, as
it is thought from the perspective of future thinking.
The horizon is “the openness that surrounds
us” (ibid., p. 64). But how are we to think this horizon as openness? We can
think of it, says Heidegger, as a Gegend, a “region”. As von Herrmann
affirms, what Heidegger names here Gegend is also called “the unconcealed,
the truth… of be-ing”
[6] (1994, p. 381). In the
Conversation, the region is defined by Heidegger as “an enchanted region
where everything belonging there returns to that in which it rests” [durch deren Zauber alles, was ihr gehört, zu
dem zurückkehrt, worin es ruht] (1966a, p. 65).[7]
The region Heidegger mentions is not one
amongst others, but is “the region,” “the region of all regions” (1966a, p. 65).
We have seen Heidegger leading us to the region from the concept of horizon and
what we call horizon is “the side facing us of an openness which surrounds us”
(ibid., p. 64). But what this openness is in itself has not yet been said. This
openness in itself, “the region of all regions,” is “that which comes to meet
us” (ibid., p. 65); as soon as we begin to think of it as “the region,” it
reveals itself as “that which comes to meet us.” It reveals itself as a movement
that “comes to meet us” and enacts the possibility of the relation with man. The
word assigned by Heidegger to the region of all regions, to the openness in
itself, is an ancient German form for the word Gegend, that is, ‘Gegnet’. Gegnet refers to the acting of Gegnet towards the being of Dasein. We
could say that Gegnet is the
essential movement that relates and determines a relation to the being of
Dasein.
As Fabris (1983) points out, the words “Gegend” and “Gegnet”, as well as the verbal forms “gegnen” and “vergegnen”, belong to the same root “gegen”, which originally indicates “a
dynamic opposition, temporally or spatially occurring.”[8] In the English edition, Gegnet is translated as the phrase
“that-which-regions,” since, as the translators point out, in English there is
no “analogous variant”[9] which could translate the German word,
retaining the idea of movement implied by it. The concept of movement implied in
this word enhances a fundamental element proper to Gegnet. How does Heidegger characterize
Gegnet?
Gegnet is said to be “an abiding expanse
which, gathering all, opens itself, so that in it openness is halted and held,
letting everything merge in its own resting” (Heidegger 1966a, p. 66). With this
statement we are further pushed to let go of our common way of referring to
something as something. Here the meaning of that-which-regions enriches with a
‘structure’ which is fundamentally a relation that lets “everything merge in its
own resting.” Gegnet is the “abiding
expanse,” “die verweilende Weite.” In
this statement, it is worthwhile stressing the meaning implied in the German
words that merge a temporal and spatial connotation. Gegnet, says Heidegger, is a “Weite”. As Fabris (1983) observes, the
twofold meaning of this word, as “immeasurable, undetermined space” and as
“distance,” is combined in Heidegger’s use of the word. In this dialogue, Fabris
continues, the term “Weite refers to
what comes inceptually from an undetermined distance, it refers to what ‘gives
itself from far away’.”[10]
Gegnet is not only a “Weite”: it is a “verweilende Weite,” which adds a
temporal aspect to it. “Verweilen”
means to abide, to linger, to remain, to dwell. Gegnet is not only an original movement.
It comes from an undetermined distance and keeps gifting itself to us, as it
remains, dwells, abides temporally as original openness, as “an enchanted region
where everything belonging there returns to that in which it rests”[11] (Heidegger 1966a, p. 65). It
is “an expanse and an abiding. It abides into the expanse of resting. It expands
into the abiding of what has freely turned towards itself” (ibid., p. 66).
In these lines Heidegger plays the
‘symphony’ of the essential swaying of Gegnet. The essential swaying of Gegnet is expressed by the musicality,
by the movement, expressed by the words, by their interplay with one another.
This interplay expresses here the sound of the essential swaying of be-ing that
the dialogue, as an interplay of thinking engaged with the truth of be-ing, lets
emerge.
In its essential swaying, the Gegnet — another name for the truth of
be-ing — moves towards and “comes
to meet us”; but, as Heidegger points out, it seems that this coming forth of Gegnet is rather a “drawing back” from
us (ibid., p. 66). We recognize it
as something that draws back from us. In coming forth it creates a distance. It
creates, or perhaps reveals, a space/time, an expanse in which things themselves
also do not have the character of objects anymore. They loose their nature of
means and return to their nature of being as tree, stone, flower. They return to
that moment that seems to be the absence of time — in the sense of sequence of
moments — and emerges as time-space
within which they simply are and rest.
The openness itself, is also identified as
“die Weite des Fernen,” “the expanse
of distance” (Heidegger 1966a, p. 68). Gegnet is the vastness into which
thinking as waiting finds that ‘while’ in which it rests, “the abiding in which
it remains” (ibid., p. 68). Remaining in the proximity of the expanse means
turning back towards the openness itself. This turning back is a “returning” [Zurückkehren] towards the openness, an
openness that is “that for which we could do nothing but wait” (ibid.) The
openness itself is Gegnet, and when
we think, that is, when we wait upon Gegnet, we are “let-in” by Gegnet into Gegnet. Thinking is no longer
representing. Thinking becomes “coming-into-the-nearness-of distance” [das In-die-Nähe-kommen zum Fernen]
(ibid.). Echo of the Enowning? In the language of be-ing-historical thinking, we
could say that we have been getting closer, and yet we are already there, in
that moment in which the enowning occurs and reveals itself. It seems like the
openness lets us in and allows us to rest in it, where resting means to turn
back to that to which we belong, and in so doing we are allowed to be our
innermost being, to be Da-sein.
In the Conversation we are on our
way towards the other beginning of thinking. We are again preparing and carrying
out the crossing from the first beginning of thinking to the other beginning. We
move from the relation between man and being as beingness, to the relation in
which the openness itself moves towards us. It is not a matter of transcending
to a different level of being, but of man receiving his essence, in the sense of
returning to his nature of thinking being, by means of his relation to Gegnet. In this relation, and just in
this relation, the human being can fully be himself.
At this point, let me recall for a moment
what we have been saying. We have seen that waiting means to be free from
thinking as representing. It means to be let-in into the openness itself;
waiting “moves into openness without representing anything” (Heidegger 1966a, p.
69); and in waiting, in being freed from representing, we “let ourselves in” [Sicheinlassen] (ibid.) into Gelassenheit, in the sense of being open
to Gelassenheit, in and through waiting. The fact that
we are let-in into Gelassenheit is in
fact a being let-in into Gegnet, by
Gegnet itself. The openness that we
experience, and to which we are released, is disclosed by means of the dialogue,
as well as something else which is “as inconspicuous as the silent course of a
conversation that moves us” (ibid., p. 70). Lovitts writes:
the speaking
that has already taken place has manifested a self-authenticating happening of
disclosure such that those who in thinking together have carried that speaking
forward are united in the hearing of that happening’s fresh arrival and can both
witness to and reinforce its self-authentication by bringing it to utterance not
merely through self-contained individual statements but through the confirmatory
medium of anthiphonal speech. (1995, p. 601)
The dialogue leads us on a path towards Gelassenheit, a path that in its
unfolding appears to be Gelassenheit
itself. Gelassenheit is revealed
to be the path, and also the way in which we move on this path. As Heidegger
asks: Where does this path go? And where does our moving end? Where does it
rest? “Where else but in that-which-regions, in relation to which releasement is
what it is” (1966a, p. 70). Gelassenheit, Heidegger affirms, is what
it is only in relation to ‘Gegnet’.
What does Heidegger mean with this statement? We are getting closer to Gelassenheit as “releasement to
that-which-regions.”
Releasement to
That-Which-Regions
Gelassenheit means “waiting”, and in
waiting we are in relation to the openness, and since the openness is Gegnet, it is possible to say that
“waiting” –and therefore Gelassenheit
– is a relation to Gegnet, a
“relation to that-which-regions” [Verhältnis zur Gegnet] (Heidegger 1966a,
p. 72). Indeed, it is not only a relation, but is “the relation to Gegnet” (ibid.), in that in waiting we
release ourselves to Gegnet and, in
so doing, we let Gegnet reveals
itself as Gegnet. Gelassenheit, as the relation to that-which-regions,
is a true relation; and, as Heidegger tells us, a relation is true when what is
related to, is allowed to be and held in its ownmost way of being, by what it
relates to.
Heidegger states: “The relation to
that-which-regions is waiting. And waiting means: to release oneself into the
openness of that-which-regions” (1966a, p. 72). But this does not mean that we
are brought to a place where we were not (before being brought there). It is not
that we are outside a place and then brought back to a place. As Heidegger
points out, we are never outside Gegnet. Also when we think in terms of
representing, we belong to Gegnet, in
that, as “thinking beings” [als denkende
Wesen] (ibid.), we remain in that horizon which is but the side of Gegnet that is “turned toward our
re-presenting. That-which-regions surrounds us and reveals itself to us as the
horizon” (ibid., p. 72-73).
We already noted that Gegnet reveals itself in the form of
horizon, but we can also say that it hides within the horizon. Thus, at the same
time we are within Gegnet, as it
surrounds us, we are also not in it, insofar as we have not let ourselves be
involved with it as Gegnet. This
involvement only occurs when we wait because, in waiting, says Heidegger, we are
set free, we are “released from our transcendental relation to the horizon”
(Heidegger 1966a, p. 73). This “being-released from” [Gelassensein], says Heidegger, is “the
first aspect” of what is called Gelassenheit. But it is the first not in
terms of importance, or as the first of a series. It is the first aspect, in the
sense that it is the first that we can directly refer to, as we are now mindful
of some of the elements that constitute the experience of Gelassenheit.
The fact that we refer to “being-released
from” as the first aspect does not mean that this aspect has any kind of
priority, for in Gelassenheit there
is no ranking. Moreover, we cannot simply identify Gelassenheit with this first moment,
because it neither comprehends the whole of Gelassenheit, nor is it exhaustive of
its nature. In fact, Heidegger continues, the “eigentliche Gelassenheit,” that is, the
“authentic releasement” (1966a, p.73), can happen even without this first
moment. Gelassenheit is what it is in
its whole, and it is in its whole only when it is in relation to Gegnet, that is, when it is “Gelassenheit zur Gegnet,” “releasement to
that-which-regions” (ibid., p. 74). “Releasement to that-which-regions” is what
Heidegger calls “authentic releasement.”[12]
According to Heidegger, man, in Da-sein,
“originally belongs” to that-which-regions and this is because man
is
appropriated initially to that-which-regions and, indeed, through this
itself […] In fact (supposing that it is waiting which is essential, that is,
all-decisive), waiting upon something is based on our belonging in that upon
which we wait. (1966a, p. 73-74)
Even if man is initially appropriated to
that-which-regions, man needs to be truly appropriated to it in order to be and
rest in his nature of thinking being. But if we already belong to
that-which-regions, what is the difference whether we are truthfully
appropriated to it or not? This question is asked during the conversation, and
it directs our attention to the fact that there seems to be a difference between
a ‘more originary’ (authentic) condition of thinking and being, and a more
common condition we live in as human beings. It is a condition that bespeaks of
being (authentic thinking) and not being (representing, calculative thinking) at
the same time. It is, as Heidegger puts it, a “restless to and fro between yes
and no” (1966a, p. 75).
This situation highlights the condition and
the movement proper to our existence. This is the movement that searches for
be-ing, for the truth of be-ing which, in turn, reveals itself as that
swinging-movement that reveals be-ing in its swaying of concealment and
unconcealment. What we observe here is the same movement that crosses from the
first beginning to the other beginning. The same movement that in Being and
Time (Heidegger 1996)
attempts to lead to a different comprehension of the meaning of being. It is the
difference and the distance between the ontic and the ontological. It is the
movement that impregnates the ‘event’ of the truth of be-ing. These appear to be
all different perspectives of the same “originary” movement, the “originary
turning” that is Ereignis.
Let us pause for a moment to consider a
possible misunderstanding. It could appear, from what we have been saying, that
Gelassenheit “floats in the realm of
unreality and so in nothingness, and, lacking all power of action, is a
will-less letting in of everything and, basically, the denial of the will to
live!” (1966a, p. 80). But this is not the case, for in the Gelassenheit we find something that
recalls the “power of action,” but which is not a will. It is a “resolve” [Entschlossenheit] (ibid., p. 81), but
not as an act of will that makes a decision and finds a solution to a problem or
a situation. This “resolve,” as Heidegger himself suggests, must be thought as
the one that is spoken of in Being and Time, that is, it is a “letting
oneself be called forth” (1996, p. 283) to one’s ownmost possibility of being.
“Resoluteness” — as Entschlossenheit
is translated in Being and Time — is
“authentic being a self” (1996, p.
274).
It is quite difficult to think a resolve
that is not a matter of will that moves to an action; we tend, in fact, to
consider resoluteness as a strong determination to attain something. As we read
in Heidegger’s Introduction To Metaphysics (2000), the essence of the resolve,
as he intends it, is not an intention to act; it is not a ‘gathering of energy’
to be released into action. Resolve is the beginning, the inceptual beginning of
any action moved. Here acting is not be taken as an action undertaken by Dasein
in being resolute. Rather, acting refers to the existential and fundamental mode
of being of Dasein, which is to be “care,” and which is the “primordial” being
of Dasein.
Resoluteness, in its essence, is the
remaining open of Dasein for be-ing. In the context of the Conversation, this resolve should thus
be understood as “the opening of man particularly undertaken by him
for openness…” [als das eigens übernommene Sichöffnen des
Daseins für das Offene…]
(Heidegger 1966a, p. 81). It is a resolve to remain open to be-ing, and
therefore to what is ownmost to man’s nature, which is disclosed in relation to
be-ing. This resolve is what Heidegger, in the Conversation, indicates as “releasement
to that-which-regions,” the resolve to release oneself to that-which-regions, to
remain open towards the openness itself.
Now, there is another element that pertains
to Gelassenheit: there is, in fact,
not only a resolve, but also a “steadfastness” [Ausdauer] (Heidegger 1966a, p.81) proper
to Gelassenheit. Thinking, becoming
more and more aware of its nature, and experiencing more clarity about it,
remains firm and resolute. Thinking “stands within” and “rests” in this
“composed steadfastness” (ibid., p. 81]). The “steadfastness” proper to Gelassenheit
would be
behavior which did not become a swaggering comportment, but which collected
itself into and remained always the composure of releasement [Verhaltenheit der Gelassenheit].
(Heidegger 1966a, p. 81)
Releasement rests in this “composed
steadfastness” and, by resting within it, it relates to that-which-regions and
is let-in by that-which-regions in the regioning of that-which-regions, in its
swaying. The “holding sway” of Gegnet
allows releasement to be in its ownmost being, as “releasement to
that-which-regions.” To all of this Heidegger gives the name of “in-dwelling”
[Inständigkeit] (1966a, p. 81).
“In-dwelling” refers to what in Being and Time is named ‘existence’,
which in its essence is so described by Heidegger in the Introduction to “what is
metaphysics?”:
what is meant
by ‘existence’ in the context of a thinking that is prompted by, and directed
toward, the truth of Being, could be most felicitously designated by the word
“in-standing” [Inständigkeit]. We
must think at the same time, however, of standing in the openness of Being, of
sustaining this standing-in (care), and of enduring in what is most extreme
(being toward death)…; for together they constitute the full essence of
existence… (1998a, p. 284)
Resolve, steadfastness, in-dwelling belong
all together to “authentic releasement,” that is as such, when it is in relation
to that-which-regions. Heidegger summarizes this authentic relation as
follows:
(Scientist) […]
authentic releasement consists in this: that man in his very nature belongs to
that-which-regions, i.e., he is released to it.
(Scholar): Not
occasionally, but…prior to everything.
(Scientist): The prior,
of which we really can not think…
(Teacher): …because
the nature of thinking begins there.
(Scientist): Thus man’s
nature is released to that-which-regions in what is prior to
thought.
(Scholar): […]and,
indeed, through that-which-regions itself
(1966a, p.
82-83)
During the conversation, the experience of
“that-which-regions” occurs, but while the “nature” of that-which-regions “has
neared,” Heidegger says, “that-which-regions itself seems… to be further away
than ever before” (1966a, p. 85). It is the openness itself that here opens
before us; but in its opening, the openness hides itself, and thus seems to be
“further away” from us. Perhaps Gelassenheit, says the teacher, as the
resolve to let oneself be involved with the truth of be-ing, would be — as we
have been experiencing during the conversation — a “coming near to and so at the
same time remaining distant from that-which-regions…” (ibid., p. 86). But what
would be the nearness and distance in which Gegnet conceals and unconceals
itself?
(Scholar): This
nearness and distance can be nothing outside
that-which-regions.
(Teacher): Because
that-which-regions regions all, gathering everything together and letting
everything return to itself, to rest in its own
identity.
(Scientist): Then
that-which-regions itself would be nearing and
distancing.
(Scholar):
that-which-regions itself would be the nearness of distance, and the distance of
nearness… (Heidegger 1966a, p. 86)
Here Heidegger mentions the ‘dialectic’ of
concealing and unconcealing that is the way in which be-ing in its truth, Gegnet, the openness in itself, holds
sway. Until now we have considered the nature of thinking as “(that in-dwelling releasement to
that-which-regions) which is the essentially human relation to
that-which-regions” (Heidegger 1966a, p. 87). The nature of thinking, so
expressed, is “something we presage as the nearness of distance” (ibid.). This
nearness of a distance that the nature of thinking reveals itself to be, cannot
be expressed by a ‘single’ word. Nevertheless, Heidegger stresses, during the
conversation one word echoes from the backdrop, a word that could be closer to
indicating what we have been looking for. The word is a Greek one: “`Aγχιβασίη”
(ibid., p. 88) that can be translated, as Heidegger suggests, as “going
towards,” but also — more literally — as “going near.”
Heidegger is reluctant to choose one word
to indicate what is being revealed during the conversation. A single word can
only with difficulty retain the meaning of something multidimensional.
Nevertheless, Heidegger proposes a word which, in itself, seems to remain in the
dynamic of the counter-movement of be-ing itself, and which seems to suggest
itself throughout the conversation. This word, ‘`Aγχιβασίη’, both names and does
not name the nature of thinking which is sought. Nevertheless, it remains the
word that seems best suited to let the nature of this experience emerge.
“`Aγχιβασίη” as “going toward” and “going near,” can be taken as
“moving-into-nearness’ [In-die-Nähe-gehen]… in the sense of
letting-oneself-into-nearness” [In-die-Nähe-hinein-sich-einlassen]
(Heidegger 1966a, p. 89). This “letting-oneself-into-nearness,” Heidegger
finally states, seems to be “the name for our walk today along this country
path” (ibid.).
The path towards Gelassenheit guided us into-nearness, a
nearness with which we have been involved by engaging with this path, which has
been a path of thinking, a path along which the nearness and distance of that
towards which we have being moving has being disclosing itself in our own
attempt to understand what we are looking for. Our path, which began as a
question about Gelassenheit, brought
us into the nearness of be-ing and became an experience of a
moving-into-nearness of be-ing. With this experience we are posed now before a
task that belongs to man’s nature, which is that of being a “thinking being,” a
being that meditates and thinks the truth of be-ing. The task is that of being
mindful and moving closer to that which is the closest to us, and because of
this the farthest, that is, be-ing in its truth. Thinking the truth of be-ing is
the task of thinking, and thus of man, that as “thinking being,” is called to
“in-dwell into releasement to that-which-regions.”
Reference List
Caputo, John D., (1990). The Mystical Element in Heidegger’s
Thought.
Heidegger, Martin, (1996). Being and Time. Trans. Joan Stambaugh.
------ (2001). Contributions to Philosophy
(from Enowning). Trans. Parvis Emad and Kenneth Maly.
------ (1966a). Conversation on a Country Path about
Thinking. In: Martin
Heidegger, Discourse on Thinking.
Trans. John M. Anderson and E. Hans Freund.
------ (1966b). Discourse on Thinking. Trans. John M.
Anderson and E. Hans Freund.
------ (2000). Introduction to Metaphysics. Trans.
Gregory Fried and Richard Polt
------ (1998a). Introduction to: “What Is Metaphysics?”.
In: Martin Heidegger, Pathmarks, ed.
William McNeill.
------ (1998b). Letter on “Humanism.” In: Martin
Heidegger, Pathmarks, ed. William
McNeill. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998, pp.239-276.
------ (1983). L’abbandono. Trans. Fabris Adriano.
Genova: Il Melangolo.
Herrmann, Friedrich-Wilhelm v.. (1994). Wege ins Ereignis: zu Heideggers “Beiträge
zur Philosophie.”
Lovitt, William and Harriet Brundage.
(1995). Modern Technology in the
Heideggerian Perspective. Vol. II. Lewiston/Queenston/Lampeter: The Edwin
Mellen Press.
Mulhall, Stephen, (2001). Heidegger and Being and Time.
Schürmann,
Reiner (2003). Heidegger and Meister Eckhart on Releasement. In Hubert Dreyfus
and Mark Wrathall, eds. Heidegger
Reexamined.
Vitiello, Vincenzo
(2000).“Abgeschiedenheit”, “Gelassenheit”, “Angst”. Tra Eckhart e Heidegger.
In: AAVV, Questio 1/2001. Heidegger e I Medievali.
Atti del Colloquio Internazionale Cassino
10/13 Maggio 2000. A cura di Costantino Esposito e Pasquale Porro.
Wagner, Jürgen, (1995). Meditationen über Gelassenheit.
[1] Translation
mine.
[2] Translation
mine.
[3] In the context of Heidegger’s
philosophy, we need to think this step forward as indeed a step back towards the
origin, towards the “other beginning” of
thinking.
[4] What I call here secure vagueness
can be thought of as that time-space in which “the leap” of thought mentioned by
Heidegger in the Contributions to Philosophy (from Enowning)
(2001), takes place. In this expanse, in which I claim we rest in Gelassenheit, we become aware of moving
closer to our innermost being, and this gives us a sense of being ‘at home’ -and
in this sense it gives us a sense of security. But in this secure expanse, there
is at the same time a sense of vagueness as we are open towards something that
comes towards us and that we do not know. In this sense I claim that in Gelassenheit our thought rests in a kind
of secure vagueness, that is, it remains open and free before what is to
come.
[5] Fabris Adriano, note 5, pp. 81-82.
In: Heidegger (1983)
[6] Translation
mine.
[7] In this statement, as von Hermann
(1994) suggests, the “charm” [der
Zauber] that enchants names the way in which the region acts. Cf. WiE p.
381.
[8] Fabris Adriano, note 7, p. 82. In:
Heidegger (1983).
[9] Cf.: Heidegger 1966b, p. 66, note
1.
[10] Fabris Adriano, note 8, p. 83. In:
Heidegger (1983)
[11] In German: “durch deren Zauber
alles, was ihr gehört, zu dem zurückkehrt, worin es
ruht.”
[12] The peculiar relation between Gelassenheit and that-which-regions is
named by Heidegger “Vergegnis,”
“regioning”. More specifically, Gelassenheit names the relation of
Dasein to the openness, that is, it speaks from the perspective of man as
thinking being. The same relation, but from the perspective of Gegnet towards the ‘essence’ of human
being as Gelassenheit, is called “Vergegnis,” the “regioning,” and it
highlights the perspective of Gegnet
from which the relation is moved, that is, is allowed to be. Vergegnis is a word that sums up the
essence of what we are trying to experience as Gelassenheit. It is a word coined by
Heidegger, along with its verbal form “vergegnen.” It is used by Heidegger to
gather together the meaning of Gelassenheit. It indicates the movement
that, coming from Gegnet, moves Gelassenheit towards Gegnet itself. It is both the movement
that opens and the openness that keeps open for Gelassenheit, for the waiting upon Gegnet, so that Gelassenheit, as the nature of thinking, can be
appropriated (enown) to itself, resting in its belonging to Gegnet. Vergegnis is thus another word for
“turning in enowning.”
Copyright © 2006 Minerva
All rights are reserved, but fair and good
faith use with full attribution may be made of this work for educational or
scholarly purposes.
Barbara Dalle Pezze has just been awarded a PhD in Philosophy by the
Return to Minerva (Volume 10) Main
Page Go to Top
of This Page